Notes
-
[2]
I will refer to this seminar with the name “Trust Seminar” as did its organizer, Diego Gambetta.
-
[3]
For a complete list of people contacted and interviews conducted, see Appendix 1.
-
[4]
In the ultimatum bargaining game one player, the proposer, is endowed with a sum of money. The proposer has to split it with another player, the responder. Once the proposer communicates his decision, the responder may accept it or reject it. If the responder accepts, the money is split according to the proposal; if the responder rejects, both players receive nothing. Both players know in advance the consequences of the responder accepting or rejecting the offer.
-
[5]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[6]
The distinction between procedural and substantive rationality was first drawn by Herbert Simon in 1979, which Gambetta quotes in his thesis. Substantive rationality refers to behaviour appropriate to the achievement of given goals within the limits imposed by the given conditions and constraints. It thus qualifies the results of choice for given conditions and criteria. On the contrary, procedural rationality qualifies a process of choice or the search for the right way to act: the conditions of choice are the subject of a search (Frydman [1994]).
-
[7]
I must mention here that Diego Gambetta has read the whole paper and, although he agreed with the general points, he wanted to clarify that in his view, “rational choice theory is a useful benchmark, but explanatory mechanisms which are both relevant and more realistic are a larger family” (Diego Gambetta, personal communication, February 12, 2021).
-
[8]
One can see an allusion in the name of the seminar that Gambetta organizes “Trust and Social Change” to this series.
-
[9]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[10]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 02/04/2019.
-
[11]
Interview with Edward Lorenz on 24/01/2019.
-
[12]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 02/04/2019.
-
[13]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 02/04/2019.
-
[14]
Interview with John Dunn on 31/07/2019.
-
[15]
John Dunn joined King’s College Cambridge as a student in 1961. He became a Fellow at King’s College in 1966. In 1985, at the age of 45, he was Reader in Politics at King’s College and, like Diego Gambetta, a member of the SPS. He is now Professor Emeritus of Political Theory at King’s, which he has never left.
-
[16]
Interview with Good on 17/07/2019. In 1985 David Good was a young (34 years old) lecturer in Social Psychology at Cambridge University. He became fellow at King’s College in 1988, he has not left since.
-
[17]
Interview with John Dunn on 31/07/2019.
-
[18]
Interview with David Good on 17/07/2019.
-
[19]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 24/07/2019. Partha Dasgupta a 43-year-old Fellow of St John’s College in 1985. He joined Cambridge as a Mathematics student in 1965. Three year later, in 1968, he defended his thesis in Economics at Cambridge and became a Research Fellow at Trinity Hall College, which he left in 1971. In 1985 he returned to Cambridge as a Fellow of St John’s College, a position he still holds.
-
[20]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 24/07/2019.
-
[21]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 24/07/2019.
-
[22]
Interview with David Good on 17/07/2019.
-
[23]
Interview with Diego Gambetta 02/04/2019.
-
[24]
Funded up to £120 by the SPS and £500 by King’s College Cambridge. (Diego Gambetta’s archives (DGA), Gambetta to SPS, 20/02/1986).
-
[25]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[26]
Albert Hirschman to Diego Gambetta, 30/09/1985, DGA.
-
[27]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 25/07/2019.
-
[28]
Interview with David Good on 17/07/2019.
-
[29]
Some of them can be considered as “guest of protocol”, as Lorenz (24/01/2019 interview) said: “Bernard Williams, it was perhaps almost mandatory at Cambridge to offer him an opportunity to present.”.
-
[30]
Interview with David Good on 17/07/2019.
-
[31]
Interview with Edward Lorenz on 24/01/2019.
-
[32]
Gambetta to SPS, 26/04/1985, DGA.
-
[33]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[34]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 25/07/2019.
-
[35]
See Bacharach and Gambetta [2001]. Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[36]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019. Gambetta owed the meeting of two of them to the seminar, two others participated directly or indirectly.
1. Introduction
1The seminar on Trust and Social Change was a series of research seminars held between 1985 and 1986 at King’s College Cambridge. [2] Organized by sociologist Diego Gambetta, the purpose of those meetings was to discuss “what generates, maintains, substitutes, or collapses trusting relations” (Gambetta [1988], p. ix). These seminars brought together many economists such as Partha Dasgupta, Thomas Schelling, Edward Lorenz, Frank Hahn, and academics from neighbouring social sciences such as Bernard Williams (philosophy), Niklas Luhmann (sociology), or David Good (social psychology). The content of those seminars – except for the one presented by Schelling – was published in a 1988 book edited by Gambetta called Trust, Making and Breaking Cooperative Relations. This book played a decisive role in structuring a field sometimes called the “Economics of Trust” (Laurent [2012]). Indeed, this publication marked both the advent of a theoretical interest in the notion of trust in economics and the introduction of a certain way of using game theory to approach the notion of trust in sociology. Economists such as Bachmann and Zaheer [2008], Laurent [2012] or Tazdaït [2008] have made an extensive use of some of the contributions in their historical reconstructions of the economics of trust. Yet, that they together result from a single series of seminars is usually not acknowledged. The thesis of this paper is (1) that the success of the book largely derived from its oral origins, and (2) that the seminar itself acted as an interface for interdisciplinary exchange.
2Regarding this last point. I understand interdisciplinarity in the sense of Roger Backhouse and Philippe Fontaine [2010], i.e., as situations that involve exchanges of intellectual tools. Their characterization is especially useful for the contrast they provide with the notion of multidisciplinary, which they understand as situations where researchers work in parallel on the same object but without significant interactions (and they propose to use the notion of cross-disciplinarity when it is not relevant to clearly characterize the situation).
3This article is a contribution to the scarce but growing literature on the role of seminars in the history of economics (Düppe and Weintraub [2014]; Emmet [2011]; Goutsmedt [2017]; Monneau [2018]). This literature shows that the seminar, as an object of study, makes it possible to understand the interaction between the social conditions of knowledge production and the ideas being produced. The social conditions of knowledge are difficult to document, as they often do not leave published paper footprints. In line with recent uses of oral histories projects in the history of economics (see, e.g., Cherrier and Saïdi [2018]; Svorenčík [2015]; see also Jullien [2018] for an overview of these projects), I supplemented Gambetta’s personal archives with an extensive set of interviews of participants to the seminar to reconstruct its dynamics. [3] The aim of this approach is to document the intellectual and practical conditions in which the seminar took place.
4The paper is structured as follows: I first provide a quick historical background of the notion of trust in social sciences and of how Gambetta became interested in this field. I then examine the outcomes of the seminar, in particular the 1988 book. Finally, I survey the effects that publication of this book had, both on the participants and on the economics of trust.
2. The notion of Trust in social sciences
5There is general agreement that Columbia social psychologist Morten Deutsch published in 1958 under the title “Trust and suspicion” the first post-war systematic study of the notion of trust. As he himself notes in this article “an examination of a half-dozen or more of the leading textbooks in social psychology reveals that the word “trust” does not appear in any of their indexes. So far as we know, the research summarized in this paper represents the first attempt to investigate experimentally the phenomena of trust.” (p. 265). Though involved with anti-war movements since the nuclear bombings at Hiroshima and Nagasaki, Deutsch drew on funding from the US military to carry “psychological investigations of the prisoner’s dilemma” (Erickson et al. [2013], p. 147). In this pioneering work, Deutsch carries out an experiment inspired by the prisoner’s dilemma on a group of college students. It is through this two-person non-zero-sum game, sometimes performed in one trial, sometimes in ten, that he shows that it is possible to approach the notion of trust experimentally and that there are many situations in which cooperation is empirically observed but not predicted or explained by rational choice theory. His work therefore belonged to a strand of research that was influenced by the ideological context of the Cold War along with other contributions such as the pioneering work of John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern [1944]. Despite this early interest, the notion of interpersonal trust was not more widely discussed in social sciences until the 1980s – mostly from an experimental perspective in economics and from a theoretical one in sociology.
6Although economists have occasionally mentioned trust, as in the case of Arrow who calls it an “important lubricant of a social system” ( [1974], p. 28), there was no systematic investigation of trust in economics prior to the 1980s and the advent of game theory. Although developed in the 1940s, game theory only became a widespread tool forty years later. This can be explained by the failure and decline of the general equilibrium program, as well as by the advent of a new research program in game theory applied to the social sciences: the “refinement program” (Giocoli [2003]). By contrast with the pre-1980 “classical game theory” based on perfect rationality and common knowledge (Sugden [2001]), such program aimed to refine the requirement needed to attain a unique Nash equilibrium in games and tried to do so through three different approaches: the respecification theories, the bounded rationality theories, and revisionary theories (Larrouy [2013]). Respecification theories attempted notably to transform coordination games with multiple equilibria into other types of games with unique equilibrium. In the cases where trust was initially needed for coordination, the game was transformed into one in which cooperation depends only on the players’ risk attitude, a notion with which economists are more familiar. Bounded rationality theories or revisionary theories attempted to relax in different ways the notion of perfect rationality. In these cases, the notion of trust was used as a means to go beyond the requirement of self-centered self-interest that was a typical companion of economic models based on perfect rationality.
7As Bacharach [2006] points out, the ambitions of this program were unsuccessful. This program has, however, made trust an object of analysis in economics that was then approached experimentally. Experimental economics had largely developed hand in hand with new imports from game theory, as attested by Melvin Dresher and Merrill Flood’s 1950 attempt to have their RAND colleagues Armen Alchian and John Williams play a Prisoner’s Dilemma game a hundred times in succession. In economics, Vernon Smith ran experiments on political choices (with Charles Plott in [1979] and on bidding and auctioning [1976] during the 1970s, before establishing laboratories in Arizona and Caltech respectively, see Svorenčík [2015]. Those mechanism designers tasked with working out new auctions to allocate the radio spectrum in 1994 likewise resorted to experimental tests of their designs (Guala [2001]). The importance of trust in orienting the outcome of games was also tested through several experiments. By studying a multiperiod version of the ultimatum game Werner Güth et al. [1993] have managed to show that “trust in fairness can stabilize cooperation and thereby improve efficiency” (p. 51). [4] Another example is the “trust game” (Berg et al. [1995]), in which a first subject can decide between non-cooperation (with a sure but small individual outcome) and cooperation (with a potentially larger outcome, depending on the decision of another subject). If this first subject chooses to cooperate, then a second decides whether the fruits of cooperation are equally divided with the first subject or whether he or she does not leave anything to the first subject who trusted him or her. This game was investigated in different experimental settings notably through a project research project initiated by Güth and Reinhard Tietz and financed by the German Science Association (see Güth et al. [1997]; Wendel [1994]; Konigstein and Tietz [1995]).
8As a reaction to this movement, sociology also began to focus from a theoretical angle on the notion of trust in the 1980s with the idea that “there is a large quantity of research on trust by experimental psychologists and political scientist, which, however, appears theoretically unintegrated and incomplete from the standpoint of a sociology of trust” (Lewis and Weigert [1985], p. 967). In this respect, one books attempted to place trust at the heart of sociological analysis: Niklas Luhmann’s Trust and Power [1979]. In Luhmann’s book, trust is the result of an evolutionary process: if trust exists it is not out of altruism but because it is the mechanism that most effectively enables people to exchange. In this purely theoretical book Luhmann wishes to establish the basis for a sociological study of trust by justifying two distinctions: between trust and familiarity, on the one hand and between interpersonal trust and institutional trust, on the other hand. The result is that interpersonal trust acts as a mechanism for the reduction of social complexity. The notion of trust then quickly spread in sociology, as different sociologists tried to account for trust from different theoretical perspectives. Trust has therefore been approached in several ways: “as a property either of individuals or of the emotional content, common understandings, or reciprocities of their interpersonal relationships” (Shapiro [1987], p. 625). As early as 1987, Susan Shapiro mentioned a “potpourri of definitions applied to a host units and levels of analysis” (ibid.).
9We therefore find ourselves with two distinct research programs on the same research subject: on the one hand sociology tried to apprehend interpersonal trust in a theoretical way, on the other hand economics tried to apprehend it in an experimental way by testing hypotheses from game theory. In 1984, Gambetta – then sociologist at Cambridge (U.K.) – submitted an application to organize a cross-disciplinary seminar on Trust in King’s College Cambridge. On this occasion, these two strands of research came together.
3. Gambetta and rational choice theory
10Gambetta arrived in Cambridge in 1979 as a Graduate Student after graduating in Philosophy and Social Sciences at the University of Turin. Theory always had a central place in Gambetta’s work, as he himself puts it: “Empirical work in my books has always been the slave of theory rather that in the driving seat.”. [5] His interest for the theory of rational choice developed during his PhD dissertation. Defended in 1983 in Cambridge under the supervision of sociologist and statistician Cathie Marsh (1951-1993), it was published under the title Were they pushed or did they jump? in 1987. In this first academic work Gambetta focused on what he called “individual decisions in education” (p. 1) and tried to explain the decision·making mechanisms of students who decide whether to leave school once they have passed the legal age. The central problem he addressed was to distinguish, in students’ behaviour, between what resulted from an intentional choice from what could be attributed to social determinism.
11The first part of this work was an attempt to classify the different ways in which human choice can be apprehended in the social sciences. Drawing on Elster’s Ulysses and the Sirens [1979], Gambetta differentiated between “structuralist”, “push-from-behind” and “pulled-from-the-front” approaches. The structuralist approach conceived the human action as “channelled by external constraints”, he explained (p. 8). The push-from-behind approach, although different, came to the same conclusion: “Broadly speaking, it assumes that a given piece of behaviour follows from causes, either social or psychological, that are opaque to the individual consciousness and, by acting behind their backs, push the agent towards a given course of action” (p. 11). Finally, the pull-from-behind approach conceived the individual as a rational agent. Gambetta clearly situated his work within the version of this approach that was initiated by Herbert Simon [1979] in economics and cognitive sciences, and by Jon Elster [1979] in philosophy. This version emphasized a procedural or limited kind of rationality: “the specifically human rationality is characterized by the capacity to relate to the future in contradistinction with the myopic gradient-climbing in natural selection”, Gambetta ( [1987], p. 17) wrote. [6] Therefore, from the very beginning of his career, Gambetta displayed a desire to distance himself from a certain type of sociology which, according to him “do not leave any substantial room for choice” (p. 8). Hence his early interest in rational choice theory.
12Elster played a significant role in the way Gambetta came to embrace rational choice theory. [7] From his PhD thesis onwards, Gambetta made an extensive use of Elster work’s to justify his theoretical approach. In particular, he shared Elster’s view that “the notion of rationality or in a weaker sens that of intentionality are of central importance for understanding and explaining human agency.” (p. 21). Gambetta drew on Elster’s work in his thesis, and, without having never met or spoken to him, sent him the manuscript in 1983. Elster proposed to publish it in the “Studies series in Rationality and Social Change” for which he was an editor. [8] Elster also invited Gambetta to come and meet him in Oslo in 1984, where, according to Gambetta “they became and remained friends”. [9]
13Newly-minted PhD Gambetta was recruited as Junior Research Fellow at King’s College Cambridge in 1984, and immediately set to organize the Trust Seminar. The notion of trust had never been a research topic for Gambetta prior to this seminar. As he explained, this interest came from a desire to “make sense of the persistent and apparently insoluble political and economic problem Italy has faced over the century since it became a politically united nation: the underdevelopment of most of her southern regions [...]” ( [1988], p. xi). But trust was above all a way for Gambetta to pursue and deepen his interest in rational choice theory.
14Gambetta retrospectively explained that “Trust was in a sense a challenge to self-interest, a challenge to full information, a challenge to rationality. All the challenges that were beginning to float around were nicely gelled in the notion of trust.”. [10] This is also confirmed by Edward Lorenz, an economist who presented at this seminar when he was a young Postdoctoral Research Fellow in the Department of Applied Economics at Cambridge: “[Gambetta] always tends to look for a rational explanation for any phenomenon”. [11] Thus, when Gambetta explained that he invited “different people from different disciplines of King’s College who showed enough interest in the subject” [12], he in fact meant trust as much as the ability of rational choice theory to interrogate this notion.
4. The Trust Seminar
15Organized between October 1985 and May 1986, the Trust seminar was a research seminar that took place at King’s College between 5: 00 p.m. and 7: 00 p.m. The sessions were divided into two equal parts with one hour dedicated to the presentation and one hour for discussion. The seminars gathered in average 20 to 30 people. [13]
4.1. King’s College, this “small society” [14]
16Then as now, the University of Cambridge was like an administrative layered cake. Life on the university was structured by the Colleges, 31 in number since 1977. They were, and still are, multidisciplinary and autonomous institutions with their own funding, rules of recruitment, and premises. In addition to Colleges, departments gathered teachers and researchers by discipline, sometimes further divided into committees. To take an example, a researcher like Gambetta was a Junior Research Fellow at King’s College but also a member of the Social and Political Sciences Committee (SPS), a sub-division of the Department of Economics. In this mid-1980, King’s College was considered as a large College (between 60 to 80 members according to John Dunn). [15] It was a place where members “saw each other all the time and mix in all sorts of environments.” [16] Dunn explained that this was by no means a fortuitous event. The Provost (name given to the position of Director of King’s College Cambridge) was considered a true “social entrepreneur” who always worked to strengthen this collective emulation through the organisation of daily life on the one hand, and of seminars on the other. [17]
17The daily life was organized in order to maximize the cohesion of the fellows. This was done first through meals. Lunch was and remains a major structuring event in life at King’s College. It was, in everyone’s opinion, a crucial moment to make a good impression in the eyes of the other Fellows: “you don’t want to appear a fool in their eyes, you want what you do to look interesting to them and you want to pick up quickly on what they are interested in”, David Good remembers. [18] In addition to these lunches, it was not uncommon for fellows to have dinner at the College. Everywhere at the University of Cambridge, the organization of the scientific life was embedded in social life. Dasgupta shared the same experiences and pointed out that it was not unusual for the College to become a residence for “single people and fellows whose partners did not live in Cambridge.” [19]
18Attending seminars on a daily basis was also a crucial element of the social and scientific life in Cambridge. Most interviewees consequently described Cambridge and King’s College as a “very oral place”. [20] Dasgupta referred to the seminars as “a sort of group of friends getting together”, [21] a vision that is also reflected in the words of Good when he shared his encounter with Gambetta: “I knew him through a group of friends, which was also a junior reading seminar.” [22] This proximity between the fellows eventually became a joke between members of the College: “It was a very informal little society, as my friend Pascal Boyer once said, King’s College is a place where people are very well known... to each other.” [23] The intellectual consequence of a social organization geared toward multiplying social interactions from morning to night was interdisciplinary, one emphasized by Gambetta in the foreword to his 1998 book: “The College was the donor of something immeasurably more valuable than cash: a unique environment where an interdisciplinary exchange is encouraged and facilitated by daily proximity.” (p. ix). Furthermore, the financing of the seminar relied largely on King’s College and to a lesser extent on the SPS which further encouraged cross-disciplinarity. [24]
4.2. A mostly Cambridgian casting
Reconstruction of the calendar of the Seminar on Trust and Social Change.
Reconstruction of the calendar of the Seminar on Trust and Social Change.
19The list of organised sessions showed a particularly local casting. Out of the thirteen speakers, eleven came from Cambridge University. Only Niklas Luhmann came from the University of Bielefeld and Thomas Schelling came from Harvard.
20Among the invited participants from outside of Cambridge, one can distinguish three cases. First, those who, like Elster, share some intellectual proximity with the project but could not participate for “practical reasons”. [25] One was Albert Hirschman, who declined his invitation in September 1985, claiming to be too “overburdened”. [26] Hirschman [1970, 1977] participated to the extension of rational choice theory by building on the work of Simon and Amartya Sen to propose a constructive criticism of rational choice theory (see Cot [2013]). It was mainly in his book Exit, Voice, and Loyalty that he developed the idea that rationality was limited because it was necessarily “located in a physical space, in a space of resources or in a space of coordination possibilities” (Thireau [2015]). Another was Schelling, who criticized the standard conception of game theory as a “mathematical toolbox for economics” (Giocolli [2003], p. 111), against which he attempted to “anchor game theory in the real world by highlighting the importance of social events, institutions, convention, etc.” (Larrouy [2013], p. 1). This is in particular the objective he pursued when he developed the concept of the focal point: a game solution that people tend to choose by default in the absence of communication (Schelling [1960]).
21Second, there was the case of Luhman, who was not interested in renewing rational choice theory but who had worked on the notion of trust before the seminar (Luhman [1979]). Gambetta probably sensed that Luhmann’s sociological work on trust was not incompatible with rational choice theory, because he defined trust as an interpersonal phenomenon rather than an institutional one (such as self-confidence, or confidence in the future).
22Dasgupta represents yet another type of case. Intellectually, Dasgupta showed interests in both the movement for the renewal of rational choice theory, and in game theory. He had participated in the book Utilitarianism and beyond [1982], directed by Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams. He had also collaborated with Kenneth Binmore on two books Economic Organizations as Games [1986] and The Economics of Bargaining [1987], the latter of which was then considered as “the major exposition and exploration to date of the meaning and implications of the Nash programme” (Petith [1987], p. 995). Sociologically, Dasgupta was the only member of Cambridge that Gambetta did not know personally before inviting him. The latter remembers:
“It was very unusual. A young man calls me on the phone […] He said that he would like to meet me, he was an Italian young Research Fellow at King’s College by the name of Gambetta, as you know, Diego. [...] He came to see me and explain to me that he wanted to start an all-year seminar on Trust, and he asked me if I would want to participate in this seminar.” [27]
24Although Dasgupta belonged to Cambridge University, his invitation is more similar to the ones addressed to the external scholars than to the internal ones.
25Other invited Cambridge scholars included “important figures from King’s College” [28] like Williams (Provost of King’s College), Bateson (who succeeded to Williams in 1988), Ernst Gellner. [29] Other often younger colleagues included those that Gambetta considered as friends: Lorenz, Good, Pagden. The seminar operated as a socialization space, especially in King’s College. The schedule of the seminar, from 5 to 7 p.m., was not chosen at random, it allowed a post-seminar socialization: “There was always a drink reception afterward. Quite often, several of us have dinner together. The idea was the seminar was the place where the discussion started but it went through the evening.” [30]. This post-seminar socialization was the will of Gambetta, whom Lorenz described as a true “social and scientific entrepreneur” [31]. Indeed, it was Gambetta who asked the SPS for an extension of funding to pay for the dinner for thirteen people after each seminar. [32] It was also Gambetta who proposed to the speakers to transform the seminar into a collective book as early as January 1986, when the seminar was not yet halfway through.
26The casting was thus influenced both by the Cambridge socialization tradition and the intellectual agenda that Gambetta thought should unify contributions. Philosopher Williams proposed to use game theory in order to reflect on the “motivation [s] to cooperate” (Williams in Gambetta [1988], p. 4) and on how one can derive the social conditions for cooperation from these motivations. Ethologist Patrick Bateson drew a parallel between cooperation among animals and among humans. He proposed “an evolutionary path through which trust may have emerged as an aspect of awareness and an essential element of human cooperation” (Gambetta [1988], p. xi). Social psychologist Good presented some experiments on the Trucking Game. Originally invented by Deutsch and Krauss [1960], it considered two manufacturers transporting some product to a sale point by road. Two roads could be used, but the shortest route could only be used by one truck at the time, so that defining a transportation schedule required some cooperation. It is within this framework that Good analysed “the implications of a wide spectrum of social-psychological evidence for the notion of trust and for the rationality of its manifestations” (Ibid.) Dasgupta focused on repeated interaction within the framework of game theory. The aim was to show that trust is a particular resource that grows as it is consumed. Political scientist Dunn presented a comparative study of different political systems and the multiple forms that trust could take within them. His analysis led him to believe that rationality alone cannot explain trust.
27Other presentations likewise dealt with trust, but in more empirical and historical ways. Historian Anthony Pagden focused on Spanish rule in eighteenthcentury Naples. He described the ways in which trust can be intentionally destroyed for the purpose of domination. Political scientist Geoffrey Hawthorn dealt with the question of whether and how vicious circles unconducive to economic development can be broken and overridden using examples from India or South Korea. Social anthropologist Ernest Gellner argued that anarchy, the absence of a centralized authority, can be productive rather than destructive for trust and cohesion. Economist Edward Lorenz reported how trust was built up between French shipbuilding firms and their subcontractors. Finally, social anthropologist Keith Hart discussed how migrants in Ghana identify safe economic relations. The contributions of the seminar were therefore either focused on the rationality of trust, or on how institutions influence trust relationships. The intellectual consistency of the seminar can also be deduced from the list of scholars that Gambetta selected to attend the sessions.
28It is interesting to note that Gambetta arranged people on this list either by College Department or by discipline. If we exclude “protocol guests” from King’s or from SPS, economists were over-represented. Two of these economists were especially thanked for their “frequent and illuminating contributions to the discussion” (Gambetta [1988], p. x) in the foreword of the 1988 book: Frank Hahn and Ugo Pagano. An honour that was by no means insignificant since they were, with Tony Tanner, a researcher in literature, the only ones to be mentioned in this way. Frank Hahn had also participated in the collective book Utilitarianism and beyond directed by Sen and Williams [1982]. In this book, Hahn’s approach is linked to that of Dasgupta, both “pointed to specific difficulties with utilitarianism and these would require relaxing the un-compromising narrowness of the utilitarian vision, but possibility not a rejection of the entire approach” (Sen and Williams [1982], p. vii). In his thesis supervised by Robert Rowthorn, who was also invited to participate in the Trust Seminar, Ugo Pagano was very critical of economists who considered rationality as a simple relation between means and ends. To him “if this relation is interpreted in the unnecessarily restrictive way that means cannot also be ends, prescribing and ascribing rationality to others, this can turn the economist into a modern vision of a conservative priest – a role to which I profoundly object.” (Pagano [1985], p. 176). Having established the institutional framework of the seminar and the way Gambetta formed its cast around its research program, we will now focus on the content and effects of the seminar.
Trust Seminar Guest List
Trust Seminar Guest List
5. From multidisciplinarity to interdisciplinarity
29The 1988 book contained thirteen chapters: twelve seminars contributions and a concluding article by Gambetta. It quickly became a must read. In his book Landmark Papers on Trust [2008], Reinhard Bachmann republished three chapters from the 1988 in the section “Origins of trust research”: those by Gambetta, Dasgupta and Luhmann. The book both contributed to turn game theory into a legit method for sociologist, and trust into a legit object of study for economists.
5.1. Game theory as a sociological method
30Gambetta had never used game theory before these seminars. Meeting Dasgupta was decisive in his adoption of this method. As he himself recounted in retrospect: “Partha Dasgupta was important because he made me understand how you can use game theory in a very intelligent way. [...] he had a way to reason about economics which I found very very inspiring.”. [33]
31The influence of game theory in the seminar was clearly reflected in Gambetta’s concluding chapter, “Can We Trust Trust.” Although it was written by Gambetta, it can be studied as a quasi-collective work to the extent that Gambetta explained that he wished to “reconstruct what seem to me the central question about trust that the individual contributions presented in this volume raise and partly answer” (Gambetta [1988], p. 213). He also took care to specify in a footnote that “in the essay converge not just several of the ideas which contributors have published in this volume but also those which were patiently expressed in conversation, and thanks to which my reflections on trust were shaped and reshaped” (Ibid.). In this article trust is defined as “a particular level of subjective probability with which an agent assesses that another agent or group of agents will perform a particular action, both before he can monitor such action (or independently of his capacity ever to be able to monitor it) and in a context in which it affects his own action (see Dasgupta and Luhmann in particular, this volume)” (p. 217). This approach was vastly different from what Gambetta proposed in his own chapter – “Mafia, the Price of Distrust” – in which there was neither a question of trust as a subjective probability nor even a mention of game theory. Other attendants were equally enticed by this new method that they had not previously encountered. One example was Robert Rowthorn who, according to Dasgupta: “changed his opinion on how to do economics [...] [and] got taken by the game theorist’s approach.” [34].
Number of citations per chapter in order of appearance in the book.
Number of citations per chapter in order of appearance in the book.
32Game theory was to have a profound impact on Gambetta’s research and his approach of trust. It was with Michael Bacharach, a game theorist, that he produced the work that he considered “the most accomplished of my contributions on this notion.” [35] The vision of the game theory of Bacharach was close to that of Schelling in that they “shared an apparently identical assessment of game theory’s limitations, and both attempted to surpass them. [...] [Bacharach] tried through his entire career to avoid traditional game theory’s pitfalls unable to account for human behaviour through its approach in terms of perfect rationality and common knowledge, by investigating the epistemic assumptions in games, the consequences of an idealized conception of player’s reasoning, and lastly, individualism in game theory” (Larrouy [2013], p. 2). Bacharach and Gambetta jointly received two research grants: one for 1994-1996 from the Economic and Social Research Council and the other for 2000-2001 from the Russel Sage Foundation. In their 2001 article, Bacharach and Gambetta combined game theory and signalling theory. The idea behind this association is that during interactions everyone had a “all-thing considered” payoff. That payoff structure differs from the one constructed with the assumption that the individual is rational and selfish. In their “all thing considered” payoff the individual considers a set of ethical and social considerations. For trust to be created between two people it is necessary to send to the other person signs, or “manifesta”, to indicate our own payoff structure. Therefore, trust is defined in line with the notion of subjective probability mentioned above as a “particular belief, which arises in games with a certain payoff structure.” (Bacharach and Gambetta [2001], p. 148).
33While the seminar space allowed the game theory method to move, in this case from economics to sociologists, the subject of this seminar – the notion of trust – did the opposite.
5.2. Trust as an economic object
34The seminar created a space that allowed participants to grasp objects that were not commonly investigated in their respective disciplines. In economics, it was with the publication of the book that trust became a bona fide theoretical object in economics. Two articles in the 1988 book deserve special attention in this regard. The first one is Dasgupta’s “Trust as a Commodity”. It was the first economic article to mobilize game theory to explicitly discuss trust. In this article Dasgupta defined trust “as a subjective probability” (p. 62) in a way that likely influenced the definition offered in Gambetta’s conclusion. This article also broadened the category of social dilemma games through adding trust games that were subsequently used by experimental economists (Camerer and Weigelt [1998]; McCabe et al. [2003]). The second chapter deserving special attention is the concluding chapter written by Gambetta “Can We Trust Trust.” This article determined how economic theory subsequently addressed this notion of trust and shaped the debates that arose from the introduction of this new object. In line with Luhmann’s contribution, Gambetta discuss trust as a relation between a person and another person (or a group of persons). This was to become the notion of trust at the heart of the debates in economics. It was for example the one referred to as “tripartite” trust by Russel Hardin [1993], in his influential article “The Street-Level Epistemology of Trust”. The latter made explicit reference to Gambetta’s work and more generally to the Trust seminar (he cited 7 of the 13 chapters of the 1988 book, which account for more than 20 % of the total references in his article). Oliver Williamson [1993] also mentioned the trust seminar in his article “Calculativeness, trust and economic organization.” He framed the whole article as an attempt to “explicate what Diego Gambetta has referred to as “the elusive notion of trust” (p. 453), a quote he took from the introduction to the 1988 book. In this article, Williamson argued that trust can, and should be, considered as an objective probability in economics. Trust then becomes the result of a calculative process, which is what led Williamson to reject the very term trust since “calculative trust is a contradiction in terms” (p. 463). Worse, as the use of the concept of trust in economics only “muddies the (clear) waters of calculativeness” (p. 471), it would therefore be necessary to substitute the notion of trust for that of risk. Williamson’s article pointed to what would become the major debate in trust research: is trust a reflection of risk or a reflection of uncertainty? These two major antagonistic positions have been at stake in numerous approaches: incomplete contract theory, reputation models, Bayesian games theory, experimental economics, transaction cost theory or the economics of convention. Several participants to the seminar took a clear stance in this debate. Like Bacharach and Gambetta in the article “Trust in Sign” [2001], we have already discussed, or like Dasgupta and Lorenz who also refused to reduce trust to risk. Dasgupta made trust an element of social capital while refusing to see the social world as stable and certain (Dasgupta [2009, 2011]). Lorenz was extremely critical of the theory of incomplete contracts which, according to him, inevitably reduced trust to risk (Lorenz [1992, 1999]).
6. Conclusion
35In conclusion, I would like to underline how the seminar played the role of an interface in the production of knowledge. The seminar was an interface because it created a space, both physical and temporal, that allowed for exchanges. While this interface had a fairly short lifespan, it had lasting effects. Not only did Gambetta later cite “Schelling, Bacharach, Dasgupta, Elster and Williams” as the scholars that most influenced his thinking, but conversely, the research of all these scholars was influenced by the ideas debated during the seminar. [36] Gambetta to this day continues to research trust and trustworthiness in various domains and by different methods (Gambetta and Flashman [2014]; Gambetta and Morisi [2020]). Finally, the seminar was also a disciplinary interface. It transformed multidisciplinary work, i.e., the coexistence of various modelling traditions and objects, into a genuinely interdisciplinary research program in which these methods and objects were absorbed by other disciplines. Fontaine has shown that economics “has appeared more cross-disciplinary though economists, unlike psychologists, tend to equate interdisciplinary relationships with proselytizing their own analytical framework to other social scientists” ( [2015], p. 3). In a sense, this phenomenon is a quite clear in the seminar studied here, with the game theoretical approach from economics imposing itself as a relevant analytical framework to study an object – interpersonal trust – that was initially conceived within sociology.
Appendix 1 – List of interviews conducted.
With the speakers:
36Edward Lorenz – 24/01/2019 – Face to face meeting in Nice (France).
37Diego Gambetta – 02/04/2019 and 03/04/2019 – Face to face meeting in Torino (Italy).
38David Good – 17/07/2019 – by Visio conference.
39Partha Dasgupta – 25/07/2019 – by Visio conference.
40John Dunn – 31/07/2019 – by Visio conference.
41Anthony Pagden – By mail.
With participants who did not present (only by mail):
42Alan Macfarlane
43Bob Evans
44Bianca Fontana
45Chris Tanner
46Colin Sumner
47David Canning
48Hugh Mellor
49Paul Ryan
50Quentin Skinner
51Ross Harrison
52Stephan Collini
53Sue James
54Sylvana Tomaselli
55Tony Giddens
Bibliographie
References
- ARROW K. [1974], The limits of Organizations, New York, W.W. Norton & Company.
- BACHARACH M. [2006], Beyond Individual Choice, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
- BACHARACH M., GAMBETTA D. [2001], Trust in Signs, in: Cook K.S. (ed.), Trust in society, New York, Russell Sage Foundation, 148-184.
- BACHMANN R., ZAHEER A. [2008], Landmark Papers on Trust, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar.
- BACKHOUSE R., FONTAINE P. (eds.) [2010], The History of the Social Sciences since 1945, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- BERG J., DICKHAUT J. and MCCABE K. [1995], Trust, Reciprocity, and Social History, Games and Economic Behavior, 10 (1), 122-142.
- BINMORE K., and DASGUPTA P. (eds.) [1986], Economic Organizations as Games, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
- BINMORE K., and DASGUPTA P. [1987], The Economics of Bargaining, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
- CAMERER C., WEIGELT K. [1988], Experimental Tests of a Sequential Equilibrium Reputation Model, Econometrica, 56 (1), 1-36.
- CHERRIER B., SAÏDI A. [2018], The Indeterminate Fate of Sunspots in Economics, History of Political Economy, 50 (3), 425-481.
- COT A. [2013], Albert O. Hirschman (1915-2012): la Résistance à tout Prix, Œconomia, History, Methodology, Philosophy, 3 (3), 459-486.
- DASGUPTA P. [2009], Trust and Cooperation among Economic Agents, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 364 (1533), 3301-3309.
- DASGUPTA P. [2011], A Matter of Trust: Social Capital and Economic Development, in: Lin J. and Plescovik B. (eds.), Annual World Bank Conference on Development Economics (ABCDE) – Global 2010: Lessons from East Asia and the Global Financial Crisis, Washington DC, World Bank, 119-155.
- DÜPPE T., WEINTRAUB E. R. [2014], Siting the New Economic Science. The Cowles Commission’s Activity Analysis Conference of June 1949, Science in Context, 27 (3), 453-483.
- DEUTSCH M. [1958], Trust and Suspicion, Journal of Conflict Resolution, 2, 265-279.
- DEUTSCH M., KRAUSS R. [1960], The Effect of Threat upon Interpersonal Bargaining, The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 61 (2), 181-189.
- ELSTER J. [1979], Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in Rationality and Irrationality, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- EMMET R. [2011], Sharpening Tools in the Workshop: The Workshop System and the Chicago School’s Success, in: Van Horn R., Mirowski P. and Stapleford T. A. (eds.), Building Chicago Economics: New perspectives on the History of America’s Most Powerful Economics Program, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 93-115.
- ERICKSON P., KLEIN J., LEMOV R., STURM T., GORDIN M., DASTONON L. [2013], How Reason Almost Lost Its Mind: The Strange Career of Cold War Rationality, Chicago, University of Chicago Press.
- FONTAINE P. [2015], Introduction: The Social Sciences in a Cross-disciplinary Age, Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 51 (1), 1-9.
- FRYDMAN R. [1994], Quelles Hypothèses de Rationalité pour la Théorie Économique?, Cahiers d’économie politique, 24-25, 16-17.
- GAMBETTA D. [1987], Were They Pushed or Did They Jump?, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- GAMBETTA D. (ed.) [1988], Trust: Making and Breaking Cooperative Relations, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
- GIOCOLI N. [2003], Modelling Rational Agents. From Interwar Economics to Early Modern Game Theory, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar.
- GOUTSMEDT A. [2017], Stagflation and the Crossroad in Macroeconomics: The Struggle between Structural and New Classical Macroeconometrics, Documents du travail du Centre d’Économie de la Sorbonne.
- GUALA F. [2001], Building Economic Machines: The FCC Auctions”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 32 (3), 453-477.
- GÜTH W., OCKENFELS P., WENDEL M. [1993], Efficiency by Trust in Fairness? Multiperiod Ultimatum Bargaining Experiments with an Increasing Cake, International Journal of Game Theory, 22, 51-73.
- GÜTH W., OCKENFELS P., WENDEL M. [1997], Cooperation Based on Trust. An Experimental Investigation”, Journal of Economic Psychology, 18 (1), 15-43.
- HARDIN R. [1993], The Street-Level Epistemology of Trust, Politics and Society, 21 (4), 505-529.
- HIRSCHMAN A. [1970], Exit, Voice and Loyalty: Responses to Decline in Firms, Organizations and States, Cambridge (Mass), Harvard University Press.
- HIRSCHMAN A. [1977], The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before its Triumph, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
- JULLIEN D. [2018], Interviews: Some Methodological and Historiographical Issues of Oral Sources, in: Düppe T. and Weintraub E.R. (eds.), Contemporary Historiography of Economics, London, Routledge, 37-56.
- KONIGSTEIN M., TIETZ R. [1995], Profit Sharing in an Asymmetric Bargaining Game, Working Paper, Humboldt University, Berlin, and Johann Wolfgang Goethe University, Frankfort am Main, Germany
- LARROUY L. [2013], Bacharach’s Variable Frame Theory’: A legacy from Schelling’s Issue in the Refinement Program, Documents de travail GREDEG.
- LAURENT E. [2012], L’Économie de la confiance, Paris, La Découverte.
- LEWIS D., WEIGERT A. [1985], Trust as a Social Reality, Social Forces, 63, 967-985.
- LORENZ E. [1992], Flexible Production Systems and the Social Construction of Trust, Politics and Society, 21, 307-324.
- LORENZ E. [1999], Trust, Contract and Economic Cooperation, Cambridge Journal of Economics, 23, 301-315.
- LUHMANN N. [1979], Trust and Power, New York, John Wiley & Sons.
- MCCABE K. A., RIGDON M. L., SMITH V. L. [2003], Positive Reciprocity and Intentions in Trust Games, Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 52 (2), 267- 275.
- MONNEAU E. [2018], Le séminaire comme Dispositif Collectif Académique Transitoire: le Cas du Séminaire Aftalion en Économie (1963-1974), Raisons Politiques, 71 (3), 81-102.
- MORGENSTERN O., VON NEUMANN J. [1944], Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
- PAGANO U. [1985], Work and Welfare in Economic Theory, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
- PETITH H. [1987], The Economics of Bargaining (review), The Economic Journal, 97 (388), 995-996.
- PLOTT C., SMITH V.L. [1979], Further Comments on the Application of Laboratory Experimental Methods to Political Choice, in: Russell C.S. (ed.), Collective Decision Making, Baltimore, Johns Hopkins Press, 167-169.
- SCHELLING T. [1960], The Strategy of Conflict, Cambridge (Mass), Harvard University Press.
- SEN A., WILLIAMS B. (eds) [1982], Utilitarianism and Beyond, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de L’Homme.
- SHAPIRO S. [1987], The Social Control of Impersonal Trust, American Journal of Sociology, 2 (3), 203-264.
- SIMON H. [1979], Models of Thought Vol. 1, New Haven, Yale University press.
- SMITH V. [1976], Bidding and Auctioning Institutions: Experimental Results, in: Y. Amihud, (ed.), Bidding and Auctioning for Procurement and Allocation, New York, New York University, 43-64.
- SUGDEN R. [2001], The Evolutionnary Turn in Game Theory, Journal of Economic Methodology, 8 (1), 113-130.
- SVORENČÍK A. [2015], The Experimental Turn in Economics: A History of Experimental Economics, Utrecht School of Economics Dissertation Series #29.
- TAZDAÏT T. [2008], L’Analyse Économique de la Confiance, De Boeck.
- THIREAU T. [2015], Albert O. Hirschman ou la Possibilité d’Analyser les Conflits, Revue Juridique Nîmoise, 7.
- WENDEL M. [1994], Rationality and Speculation – An Experimental Study of Two Interdependent Markets with Incomplete Information, Working Paper, Johann Wolfgang Goethe University, Frankfort am Main, Germany.
- WILLIAMSON O. [1993], Calculativeness, Trust and Economic Organization, The Journal of Law & Economics, 36 (1), 453-486.
Notes
-
[2]
I will refer to this seminar with the name “Trust Seminar” as did its organizer, Diego Gambetta.
-
[3]
For a complete list of people contacted and interviews conducted, see Appendix 1.
-
[4]
In the ultimatum bargaining game one player, the proposer, is endowed with a sum of money. The proposer has to split it with another player, the responder. Once the proposer communicates his decision, the responder may accept it or reject it. If the responder accepts, the money is split according to the proposal; if the responder rejects, both players receive nothing. Both players know in advance the consequences of the responder accepting or rejecting the offer.
-
[5]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[6]
The distinction between procedural and substantive rationality was first drawn by Herbert Simon in 1979, which Gambetta quotes in his thesis. Substantive rationality refers to behaviour appropriate to the achievement of given goals within the limits imposed by the given conditions and constraints. It thus qualifies the results of choice for given conditions and criteria. On the contrary, procedural rationality qualifies a process of choice or the search for the right way to act: the conditions of choice are the subject of a search (Frydman [1994]).
-
[7]
I must mention here that Diego Gambetta has read the whole paper and, although he agreed with the general points, he wanted to clarify that in his view, “rational choice theory is a useful benchmark, but explanatory mechanisms which are both relevant and more realistic are a larger family” (Diego Gambetta, personal communication, February 12, 2021).
-
[8]
One can see an allusion in the name of the seminar that Gambetta organizes “Trust and Social Change” to this series.
-
[9]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[10]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 02/04/2019.
-
[11]
Interview with Edward Lorenz on 24/01/2019.
-
[12]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 02/04/2019.
-
[13]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 02/04/2019.
-
[14]
Interview with John Dunn on 31/07/2019.
-
[15]
John Dunn joined King’s College Cambridge as a student in 1961. He became a Fellow at King’s College in 1966. In 1985, at the age of 45, he was Reader in Politics at King’s College and, like Diego Gambetta, a member of the SPS. He is now Professor Emeritus of Political Theory at King’s, which he has never left.
-
[16]
Interview with Good on 17/07/2019. In 1985 David Good was a young (34 years old) lecturer in Social Psychology at Cambridge University. He became fellow at King’s College in 1988, he has not left since.
-
[17]
Interview with John Dunn on 31/07/2019.
-
[18]
Interview with David Good on 17/07/2019.
-
[19]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 24/07/2019. Partha Dasgupta a 43-year-old Fellow of St John’s College in 1985. He joined Cambridge as a Mathematics student in 1965. Three year later, in 1968, he defended his thesis in Economics at Cambridge and became a Research Fellow at Trinity Hall College, which he left in 1971. In 1985 he returned to Cambridge as a Fellow of St John’s College, a position he still holds.
-
[20]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 24/07/2019.
-
[21]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 24/07/2019.
-
[22]
Interview with David Good on 17/07/2019.
-
[23]
Interview with Diego Gambetta 02/04/2019.
-
[24]
Funded up to £120 by the SPS and £500 by King’s College Cambridge. (Diego Gambetta’s archives (DGA), Gambetta to SPS, 20/02/1986).
-
[25]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[26]
Albert Hirschman to Diego Gambetta, 30/09/1985, DGA.
-
[27]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 25/07/2019.
-
[28]
Interview with David Good on 17/07/2019.
-
[29]
Some of them can be considered as “guest of protocol”, as Lorenz (24/01/2019 interview) said: “Bernard Williams, it was perhaps almost mandatory at Cambridge to offer him an opportunity to present.”.
-
[30]
Interview with David Good on 17/07/2019.
-
[31]
Interview with Edward Lorenz on 24/01/2019.
-
[32]
Gambetta to SPS, 26/04/1985, DGA.
-
[33]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[34]
Interview with Partha Dasgupta on 25/07/2019.
-
[35]
See Bacharach and Gambetta [2001]. Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019.
-
[36]
Interview with Diego Gambetta on 03/04/2019. Gambetta owed the meeting of two of them to the seminar, two others participated directly or indirectly.