Notes
-
[1]
See the contribution by Françoise Forges in this volume.
-
[2]
All cited results with no further reference given are from the original paper by Aumann [1974].
-
[3]
Every probability measure on a complete and separable metric space is the distribution of a random variable from [0, 1] with the uniform distribution. This is Theorem 3.2 by Billingsley [1971]. To obtain a random variable on an atomless probability space with uniform distribution on [0, 1], one can use the fact that every atomless measure has a convex range, see Theorem 10.52 of Aliprantis and Border [2006], or just Lemma 4.1, to obtain an independent stochastic process with values in {0, 1}ℕ as the distribution of a random variable. The independent measure on P = {0, 1}ℕ is measurable isomorphic to the uniform distribution on [0, 1] by the isomorphism (outside a countable exceptional set coming from the nonuniqueness of binary representations of real numbers) ϕ: P→ [0, 1] given by \(\phi\left(\left(\omega_n\right)\right)=\sum_n \omega_n / 2^n\).
Introduction
1The first formulation of correlated equilibrium by Aumann [1974] models randomization devices explicitly and allows for players to have different subjective probability assessments about these randomization devices. Today, one usually uses the canonical formulation of correlated equilibrium introduced later by Aumann [1987], which disposes of both subjectivity and the specification of an underlying randomization device. [1]
2Aumann [1974] also proved a number of results in which the subjectivity of probability assessments plays little role. This is possible because there are enough events on which all probability assessments agree. At the heart of Aumann’s argument is his Lemma 4.1 [2] to the effect that if (T, Σ) is a measurable space and µ1,…, µn a finite family of atomless probability measures, then there exists for each α ∈ [0, 1] a measurable set E ∈ Σ such that µi(E) =…= µn(E) = α. The proof is based on Lyapunov’s convexity theorem. If each µi represents the subjective belief of player i, the lemma shows that one can construct an objective event with any prescribed probability and, consequently, a finite measurable partition with any prescribed distribution on which all beliefs agree. The same result was also proven in the context of fair division by Dubins and Spanier [1961]. Later, Border, Ghirardato and Segal [2008] used the result for finite partitions to show that a σ-algebra Σ′ ⊆ Σ exists on which all µi agree and on which the µi have range [0, 1]. Their goal was to find agreeable probabilities for randomized social choice. As is shown below, the same construction allows for an even stronger result: The µi do not just have range [0, 1]; they are actually atomless. The strengthened statement is Proposition 1 below. It is this stronger statement that can be used to generalize various arguments by Aumann [1974].
Existence of Objective Lotteries
3We take all measures to be countably additive. Let (\(\Omega, \mathcal{B}, \mu\)) be a probability space. A µ-atom is a set \(A \in \mathcal{B}\) such that μ(A) > 0 and such that for all \(B \in \mathcal{B}\) satisfying B ⊆ A either μ(B) = μ(A) or μ(B) = 0. We say that µ is atomless if there is no µ-atom. It is well known that the range of an atomless probability measure is the whole unit interval; see Theorem 10.52 of Aliprantis and Border [2006]. If \(\mathcal{B}^{\prime}\) is a sub-σ-algebra of \(\mathcal{B}\), we say that µ is atomless on \(\mathcal{B}^{\prime}\) if the restriction of µ to \(\mathcal{B}\) is atomless.
4The σ-algebra constructed in the following result is constructed in exactly the same way as by Border, Ghirardato and Segal [2008].
Proposition 1. Let µ1,…, µn be atomless probability measures on a common measurable space (Ω, ∑). Then there exists a sub-σ-algebra ∑ʹ ⊆ ∑ on which all measures agree and are atomless.
Proof. Using Lemma 4.1 or the result of Dubins and Spanier, we can partition Ω into two measurable sets on which all the measures agree and take on a value of 1/2. We can further partition these sets to obtain four measurable sets on which all the measures agree and take on a value of 1/4. We continue this way and take finite unions of all sets thus obtained. This gives us a countable sub-algebra \(\mathcal{A}\) of Σ on which all measures agree. So there is a unique extension to the σ-algebra \(\sigma(\mathcal{A})=\Sigma^{\prime}\) generated by \(\mathcal{A}\) by the Carathéodory extension theorem. Consequently, all measures agree on \(\sigma(\mathcal{A})\).
Let µ be the common restriction of the µi to \(\sigma(\mathcal{A})\). We show that µ is atomless. Let \(B \in \sigma(\mathcal{A})\) with μ(B) > 0. Choose m such that 1/2m < μ(B) and partition Ω into 2m disjoint measurable sets Bl, l = 1,…, 2m, of equal µ-measure 1/2m. By construction, this can be done. Now,
\(\mu(B)=\sum_{l=1}^{2^m} \mu\left(B \cap B_l\right).\)
So there exists l such that μ(B ∩ Bl) > 0. Since μ(B ∩ Bl) ≤ μ(Bl) = 1/2m < μ(B), there exists a measurable subset of B with smaller but positive measure.
7One can show that for a given atomless probability space, any Borel probability measure on a Polish (separable and completely metrizable) space is the distribution of a random variable on the given probability space. [3] Proposition 1 allows us, therefore, to generate arbitrary distributions on such spaces that are agreed on by everyone.
Applications to Subjective Correlated Equilibria
8This section’s notation, terminology, and setting follow Aumann [1974] closely. However, Aumann calls actions pure strategies.
9A game consists of
- A finite set N = {1, …, n} of players;
- For each i ∈ N, a nonempty, compact, and metrizable space Ai of actions of i;
- A compact, and metrizable space X of outcomes endowed with the Borel σ-algebra;
- A continuous outcome function g from \(A=\prod_{i \in \in N} A_i\) onto X.
10All these spaces were additionally assumed to be finite by Aumann [1974]. To this description of the direct strategic environment, we add the following:
- A nonempty set Ω of states of the world endowed with a σ-algebra \(\mathcal{B}\) containing the events;
- For each i ∈ N, a sub-σ-algebra \(\mathcal{I}_i\) of \(\mathcal{B}\) representing the information of i;
- For each i ∈ N, a preference order \(\succeq_i\) on the set of measurable functions from Ω to X, the lotteries.
11Throughout, we make the following assumptions:
Assumption 1. For each i ∈ N, there exists a continuous utility function ui : X → ℝ and a unique probability measure pi on (\(\Omega, \mathcal{B}\)), such that for all lotteries x and y, we have \(\mathbf{x} \succeq_i \mathbf{y}\) if and only if
\(\int_{\Omega} u_i \circ \mathbf{x} \mathrm{d} p_i \geq \int_{\Omega} u_i \circ \mathbf{y} \mathrm{d} p_i.\)
As usual, N-i stands for N \ {i}. An event \(E \in \mathcal{I}_i\) is i-secret if it is pj-independent of all events in \(\sigma\left(\bigcup_{j \in N_{-i}} \mathcal{I}_j\right)\) for all j ∈ N-i. So an i-secret event is an event that i is informed about, but that other players cannot learn anything about even if they would pool all their information. The family of i-secret events is denoted by \(\mathcal{S}_i\). In general, \(\mathcal{S}_i\) need not be a σ-algebra.
Assumption 2. For each i ∈ N, there exists a σ-algebra \(\mathcal{R}_i \subseteq \mathcal{S}_i\) on which pj is atomless for all j ∈ N.
An event E is objective if p1(E) = p2(E) = …= pn(E). We let O be the family of all objective events. In general, O need not be a σ-algebra. An event is subjective if it is not objective. A function from Ω to a measurable space is objective if it is O-measurable, that is, if the preimages of measurable sets are objective. A strategy of i ∈ N is a function si : Ω → Ai that is Ii-measurable. The strategy si is mixed if it is also Si-measurable. This represents the idea that a player’s mixed strategy, the way the term is usually used in game theory, chooses independently of what other players are doing. Usually, this is done in terms of product distributions; here, it is done in terms of σ-algebras because all randomized action choices are given in terms of random variables on an underlying space.
We identify a profile of strategies with a measurable function s : Ω → A. For each strategy profile s and i ∈ N, we let
\(H_i(\mathbf{s})=\int_{\Omega} u_i \circ g \circ \mathbf{s} \mathrm{d} p_i.\)
We let H(s) = (H1(s),…, Hn(s)) and call each point of the form H(s) a feasible payoff. We say the strategy profile s is a subjective correlated equilibrium or simply an equilibrium if for every i ∈ N and all strategies ti of i, we have
\(H_i(\mathbf{s}) \geq H_i\left(\left(\mathbf{s}_1, \ldots, \mathbf{s}_{i-1}, \mathbf{t}_i, \mathbf{s}_{i+1}, \ldots, \mathbf{s}_n\right)\right).\)
A point of the form H(s) with s being an equilibrium is an equilibrium payoff.
A Nash equilibrium payoff is simply the vector of the usual expected payoffs in a game with player space N, and player i having strategy space Si and payoff-function ui ∘ g. We first prove that the usual Nash equilibria embed as equilibria in the present framework, and thus, by the Fan-Glicksberg fixed-point theorem, equilibria do exist. The following is essentially Lemma 7.3, slightly restated.
Lemma 1. Fix a player i. For every j ≠ i, let \(\mathcal{W}_j \subseteq \mathcal{S}_j\) be a σ-algebra. Then the σ-algebras \(\mathcal{W}_1, \ldots, \mathcal{W}_{i-1}, \mathcal{I}_i, \mathcal{W}_{i+1}, \ldots, \mathcal{W}_n\) are µi-independent.
15We can now generalize Proposition 4.3. and Proposition 5.1, respectively, by Aumann [1974] to a continuum of actions.
Proposition 2. The set of Nash equilibrium payoffs coincides with the set of equilibrium payoffs of equilibria in which all strategies are objective and mixed.
Proof. First, let s be an equilibrium in objective mixed strategies and i ∈ N. Then si is a best response to s–i and, a fortiori, a best response within the class of objective mixed strategies. Since all pj are atomless on \(\mathcal{R}_i\), there exists by Proposition 1 an atomless sub-σ-algebra \(\mathcal{W}_i\) of \(\mathcal{R}_i\) on which all pj agree and are atomless. Therefore, any best response of i in the classical setting is the distribution of an objective mixed strategy measurable with respect to \(\mathcal{W}_i\). By the last lemma, only the distribution is relevant for it to be a best response for i; independent randomizations correspond to product measures as distributions. So H(s) is a Nash equilibrium payoff.
Similarly, we can again apply Proposition 1 to find for each i ∈ N a sub- σ-algebra \(\mathcal{W}_i\) of \(\mathcal{R}_i\) on which each pj agrees and is atomless. If we have any Nash equilibrium, (μi)i∈N in the classical game, we can find a \(\mathcal{W}_i\)-measurable strategy si : Ω → Ai with pi ∘ s–1i = μi. The last lemma again shows that these strategies form an equilibrium that, clearly, induces the same expected payoff.
Proposition 3. Let n = 2 and assume p1(B) = 0 if and only if p2(B) = 0 for all \(B \in \mathcal{B}\). Then for any equilibrium s in mixed strategies, there is an equilibrium t in objective mixed strategies such that H(s) = H(t).
Proof. Let (s1, s2) be an equilibrium in mixed strategies. Using Proposition 1 with \(\mathcal{R}_i\), p1 and p2, we can find an objective mixed strategy t1, such that p2 ∘ s–11 = p2 ∘ t–11. Similarly, we can find an objective mixed strategy t2 such that p1 ∘ s–12 = p1 ∘ t–12. We show that (t1, t2) is an equilibrium and H(s) = H(t). Since s2 is p1-independent of \(\mathcal{I}_1\), the expected utility of 1 depends only on the distributions of the strategies of the two players under p1. Let β be the set of maximizers of ∫ui ∘ g(⋅, x2) dp1 ∘ s–12. Then β is compact and a strategy of player i is a best response to s2 if and only if its values lie p1-almost surely in β. Consequently, p1{ω : s1(ω) ∈ β} = 1. Since both players agree on all certain events,
\(p_2\left\{\omega: \mathbf{s}_1(\omega) \in \beta\right\}=1=p_2\left\{\omega: \mathbf{t}_1(\omega) \in \beta\right\}=p_1\left\{\omega: \mathbf{t}_1(\omega) \in \beta\right\}.\)
Since s2 and t2 have the same distribution for 1, t1 is also a best response to t2. Similarly, one can show that t2 is a best response to t1 for player 2. Therefore, (t1, t2) is an equilibrium.
Limitations
20We can also discuss which arguments do not generalize. These are the arguments related to public randomization. An event E is public if it is in \(P=\bigcap_{i \in N} \mathcal{I}\). A public roulette \(\mathcal{R}\) is a sub-σ-algebra of \(\mathcal{P}\) on which all pi agree and are atomless. As a direct consequence of Proposition 1, we get the following characterization of the existence of a public roulette.
Proposition 4. A public roulette exists if and only if pi is atomless on \(\mathcal{P}\) for all i ∈ N.
22However, public roulettes are less powerful in our context. Aumann shows that the existence of a public roulette implies that for every event B, one can find a public event C with any prescribed probability that is µi-independent of B for every i ∈ N; Lemma 4.4. This guarantees the convexity of the set of equilibrium payoffs and the set of feasible payoffs when action spaces are finite; Aumann’s Proposition 4.5. However, the proof relies on every strategy profile being measurable with respect to a finite partition. This then guarantees that one can find public events independent of all strategies. The argument does not generalize to a continuum of pure strategies: Let Ω = [0, 1]3 be the unit cube with \(\mathcal{B}\) the Borel σ-algebra, p1 = p2 be the uniform distribution on the unit cube, let \(\mathcal{I}_1\) be the σ-algebra generated by the first two coordinate-functions, and \(\mathcal{I}_1\) be the σ-algebra generated by the second and third coordinate function. Then the set of public events is exactly the set of events in the σ-algebra generated by the second coordinate function. Let A1 = A2 = [0, 1], g the identity, and u1 = u2 = u be given by u1(a1, a2) = –(a1 – a2)2. There is an equilibrium in which both players simply play the second coordinate. Since the second coordinate function generates all public events, no public event is independent of the equilibrium strategies. Of course, this example only shows that the particular proof does not generalize.
Bibliography
References
- Aliprantis, C. D and Border, K. C. [2006]. Infinite Dimensional Analysis. Berlin: Springer.
- Aumann, R. J. [1974]. “Subjectivity and Correlation in Randomized Strategies,” Journal of Mathematical Economics, 1: 67–96.
- Aumann, R. J. [1987]. “Correlated Equilibrium as an Expression of Bayesian Rationality,” Econometrica, 55: 1–18.
- Billingsley, P. [1971]. Weak Convergence of Measures: Applications in Probability. Philadelphia: SIAM.
- Border, K. C., Ghiradarto, P. and Segal, U. [2008]. “Unanimous Subjective Probabilities,” Economic Theory, 34: 383–387.
- Dubins, L. E. and Spanier, E. H. [1961]. “How to Cut a Cake Fairly,” American Mathematical Monthly, 68: 1–17.
Mots-clés éditeurs : subjective probability, agreement, correlated equilibrium, objective probability
Mise en ligne 12/04/2023
Notes
-
[1]
See the contribution by Françoise Forges in this volume.
-
[2]
All cited results with no further reference given are from the original paper by Aumann [1974].
-
[3]
Every probability measure on a complete and separable metric space is the distribution of a random variable from [0, 1] with the uniform distribution. This is Theorem 3.2 by Billingsley [1971]. To obtain a random variable on an atomless probability space with uniform distribution on [0, 1], one can use the fact that every atomless measure has a convex range, see Theorem 10.52 of Aliprantis and Border [2006], or just Lemma 4.1, to obtain an independent stochastic process with values in {0, 1}ℕ as the distribution of a random variable. The independent measure on P = {0, 1}ℕ is measurable isomorphic to the uniform distribution on [0, 1] by the isomorphism (outside a countable exceptional set coming from the nonuniqueness of binary representations of real numbers) ϕ: P→ [0, 1] given by \(\phi\left(\left(\omega_n\right)\right)=\sum_n \omega_n / 2^n\).