Notes
-
[1]
First published in Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales (March, 1989) as « Intérêt, rationalité et culture : à propos d’un récent débat sur la théorie de l’action ».
For a recent debate on action theory, see J. S. Coleman, “Social Theory, Social Research, and a Theory of Action”, American Journal of Sociology, 91(6), 1986, p. 1309-1335; W. H. Sewell, Jr, “Theory of Action, Dialectic, and History: Comment on Coleman”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(1), 1987, p. 166-172; and J. S. Coleman, “Actors and Action in Social History and Social Theory: Reply to Sewell”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(1), 1987, p. 172-175. Full bibliographical references are given at the end of the article. -
[2]
In addition to Coleman’s text, the May 1986 issue of Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales included two other articles on the “State of Sociology Today” (i.e. American sociology): Immanuel Wallerstein (1986), “Marxisms as Utopias: Evolving Ideologies”, and Randall Collins (1986a), “Is 1980s Sociology in the Doldrums?” Collins’ text has also provoked a lively exchange, cf. Norman K. Denzin (1987a), “The Death of Sociology in the 1980s: Comment on Collins”, and Collins (1987), “Looking Forward or Looking Back? Reply to Denzin.”
-
[3]
Or, more precisely, the truncated and resolutely presentist representation that American sociology has formed of the utilitarians (Hume, Mill, Bentham and Adam Smith), largely under the impetus of Parsons, as Charles Camic (1979) shows. This philosophical filiation is actively claimed by Coleman (1986a, p. 1329), who sees in the “compatibility [of RAT] with the conceptual foundations that have underpinned much social thought since the political philosophers of natural law in the 17th century” one of the main merits of this paradigm and the instrument of a rapprochement that he deems necessary and beneficial between sociological theory, legal theory, and moral philosophy (cf. Coleman, 1974a).
-
[4]
Cf. Heath (1976) and the texts collected in Elster (1986).
-
[5]
Hardin (1982), Oliver (1980) and the classic of the genre by Mancur Olson (1965).
-
[6]
For example Hechter (1983, 1987).
-
[7]
See Knorr-Cetina (1981) and Wiley (1985, p. 189-195). The development of this “micro-interactionist tradition” specific to American social science is summarized by Randall Collins (1985, part 3). An overview of the main recent works in microsociology can be found in Adler, Adler and Fontana (1987) and Atkinson (1988). In addition to conversation analysis (e.g., Psathas, 1979; Heritage, 1985), it is in the sociology of emotions that the most vigorous developments are recorded (as witnessed by the creation in 1987 of a section of the American Sociological Association devoted to this specialty): for example, Kemper (1978), Shott (1979), Hochschild (1979, 1983), Denzin (1984), Lofland (1985) and the issue of the journal Symbolic Interaction edited by David D. Franks in the fall of 1985 (vol. 8, n° 2) devoted entirely to the “Sociology of Emotion”; in an anthropological vein, Lutz (1988).
-
[8]
It had been officially disowned by one of its founders, Peter Blau (1977a, 1977b), who turns to “all-macro” with Inequalitv and Heterogeneity. See also his “Preface” in the form of a volte-face to the re-edition of Exchange and Power in Social Life (Blau, 1986). This link between Coleman’s RAT and exchange theory is explicitly established by Homans (1987, 1988), who sees it as a special case of the behaviorism he has tirelessly promoted over the last three decades.
-
[9]
Przeworski (1985a, p. 379). This is also the view of Anthony Oberschall and Eric M. Leifer (1986, p. 233). On the economist side, see Hirschleifer (1985).
-
[10]
See Radnitzky and Bernholz (1987). The latest supplement to the American Journal of Sociology edited by Christopher Winship (a quantitative sociologist) and Sherwin Rosen (a Chicago School economist) entitled Organizations and Institutions: Sociological and Economic Approaches to the Analysis of Social Structures (1988) acknowledges this growing interpenetration of orthodox economics and sociology in the United States.
-
[11]
Williamson (1975, 1981), Moe (1984), Fama (1980), Pratt and Zeckhauser (1985). For an excellent critical synthesis of these currents, see Perrow (1986, chapter 7) and Francis, Turk and Willman (1983). In political sociology, rationalist positivism is led by William H. Riker and Peter C. Ordeshook (1973); see also Plott (1976), Barry (1978), and the still influential earlier works of Anthony Downs, James Buchanan, Gordon Tullock and Kenneth Arrow.
-
[12]
On the rationalist approach to social movement analysis, Obershall (1973), Fireman andGamson (1979), Olson (1982), Jenkins (1983), Tilly (1978, especially p. 24-37), and Popkin (1979). An analytical synopsis of current controversies in this area of investigation emphasizing the opposition between rational and historical-cultural or “identity” models can be found in Jean L. Cohen (1985). An interesting attempt to overcome this antinomy is made by James W. White (1988). The “monument” of rational family theory is without doubt Gary S. Becker’s A Treatise on the Family (1981), which has done more than any other work to legitimize “economic imperialism”, in the words of Kenneth Boulding (1969), in this field. See also the tellingly titled article by Ben-Porath (1980), “The F-Connection: Families, Friends, and Firms and the Organization of Exchange.” Diego Gambetta’s book, Did they jump or were they pushed? (1987) contains a synthesis of the claims of RAT in the sociology of education. For a sample of recent works in network theory which takes as its object the structures of observable relations between social or organizational positions and more or less explicitly implements a rational or utilitarian conception of action, see Burt (1982), Laumann and Knoke (1987), Wellman and Berkowitz (1988).
-
[13]
Cf. Granovetter (1973, 1974) and the seminal article “Economy Action and Social Structure: The Problem of Embeddedness” (Granovetter, 1985); the work of Harrison White (1970, 1981), Leifer (1985), Powell (1985), Sabel (198, p. 4), Stark (1986), Berg (1981), as well as the articles collected by Zukin and DiMaggio (1986); also Tilly (1984b, on Mancur Olson) and Zald (1987, on Oliver Williamson). On the emergence of economic sociology as an autonomous problematic, see Swedberg, Himmelstrand and Brulin (1987) and, in a more idiosyncratic vein, Stinchcombe (1983).
-
[14]
On “voluntarist nominalism,” see Hinckle and Hinckle (1980); on “instrumental positivism” in American sociology, Bryant (1985, chapter 5).
-
[15]
See Hirsch, Michaels and Friedman (1987), and the more ambivalent view of Oberschall and Leifer (1985, p. 251).
-
[16]
The University of Chicago can legitimately claim to be the Mecca of Rational Action Theory: it has several of the most prominent representatives of RAT on its campus (James Coleman, Gary S. Becker, George Stigler, Jon Elster, and Adam Przeworski, among others). Its sociology department is the only one in the country to offer doctoral training in RAT, which includes a battery of courses specifically designed to systematize and disseminate its teaching. James Coleman and Gary Becker conduct an annual closed seminar on “Rational Models in the Social Sciences” that is nationally renowned and brings together, two evenings a month, the Rats of the Sociology, Political Science, and Economics departments. Jon Elster is the director of the newly established Center for the Study of Ethics, Rationality, and Society, where the best representatives of utilitarian subjectivism from all continents come together. A journal dedicated to the promotion of methodological individualism and deductivist rationalism has been created under the direction of James Coleman, entitled Rationalitv and Society, the first issue of which was published in June 1989.
-
[17]
See Bourdieu (1980, p. 71-83), for a critique of the ‘imaginary anthropology’ that is at the root of Sartrean phenomenology and Elster’s version of RAT.
-
[18]
The best overall introduction to this current is the collection of texts presented by John E. Roemer (1986) under the title Analytical Marxism. Also published in this series are Jon Elster, Making Sense of Marx (1985); Adam Przeworski, Capitalism and Social Democracy (1985b); and Michael Taylor (cd.), Rationalitv and Revolution (1988). Other important books of Analytical Marxism are G.A. Cohen, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence (1978); the ultra-mathematical technical tracts of John E. Roemer, Analytical Foundations of Marxian Economic Theory (1981) and A General Theory of Exploitation and Class (1982a), and the popular textbook for the undergraduate market, Free To Lose: An Introduction to Marxist Economic Philosophy (Roemer, 1988); Philippe Van Parijs, Evolutionary Explanation in the Social Sciences (1981a); and Erik Olin Wright, Classes (1985). Two debates around the theses of the Analytical Marxists can be found in issue 4, volume 11, 1982, (on Marxism, functionalism and game theory) and issue 5, volume 15, 1986, (on the transition to socialism) of Theory and Society and in issue 3, volume 11, 1982, of Politics and Society (on Roemer’s exploitation theory).
-
[19]
The series “Studies in Marxism and Social Theory” edited by G. A. Cohen, Jon Elster and John Roemer at Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences et de l’Homme is presented in these terms: “The books in this series are intended to exemplify a new paradigm in the study of Marxist social theory. Rather than adopting a dogmatic or purely exegetical approach, they will examine and develop the theory inaugurated by Marx in the light of historical experience since then, using the tools of non-Marxist social science and philosophy. It is hoped that this will free Marxist thought from the increasingly discredited methods and presuppositions which are still widely regarded as essential to it, and that what is true and important in Marxism will thus be more firmly established.”
-
[20]
Roemer (1986, p. 2-3). Further on: “In seeking to give behavior the micro-foundations that Marxists regard as characteristic of capitalism, I believe that the instruments par excellence are the models based on rational choice: general equilibrium theory, game theory, and the arsenal of modeling techniques developed by neo-classical economics” (ibid., p. 192).
-
[21]
“To understand scientific explanation or the notion of causality, the structure of intentional action or that of social interaction, knowledge of analytical philosophy is now indispensable” (Elster, An English Marxism: About a New Interpretation of Historical Materialism, 1981, p. 746). The following passage, which closes Elster’s “Critical Note on G.A. Cohen’s analytical reading of Marx,” gives an idea of the hyperbole and rhetorical effects aimed at creating an impression of radical innovation that characterize many of the mutual comments that practitioners of Analytical Marxism grace each other with regularly – and whose metaphorical schemes (pure/stagnant air, life/death, rare/common, high/low, etc.) suffice to express the intellectual height that they assign to their collective enterprise: “With his rigorous book, each page of which deserves to be commented on passionately, [Cohen] has brought us into a landscape that we did not know. The air we breathe is no longer the stagnant atmosphere of the endless scholastic discussions that nearly ruined Marxism. It is the air of the mountains; it is scarce, but we can see clearly and far” (ibid., p. 756). For another example, see Van Parijs’ (1986-87) celebration of Roemer and Wright’s class theory in an article squarely entitled “A Revolution in Class Theory.”
-
[22]
We borrow this term from Frank Parkin (1979, p. 10).
-
[23]
Partly as a result of a hysteresis effect, RAT has not yet entered the recognized scholarly taxonomies of the universe of sociological theories in America and Britain (e.g., it is absent as such from the collection assembled by Giddens and Turner, 1987, Social Theory Today).
-
[24]
In addition to the collection edited by Cohen, Roemer, and Elster mentioned above, note the series “Studies in Rationality and Social Change” edited by Jon Elster and Gudmunt Hernes at Cambridge University Press and the “California Series on Social Choice and Political Economy” published by University of California Press under the editorship of political scientists Brian Barry, Robert H. Bates and Samuel L. Popkin.
-
[25]
This article represents both the culmination of his earlier work (as evidenced by the series of public papers from 1964 to 1983 – more than a third of which were published in economics books and journals – collected in J.S. Coleman, Individual Interests and Collective Action (1986c, in Jon Elster’s “Studies in Rationality and Social Change” series) and the programmatic introduction to Foundations of Social Theory. No introduction is needed here to James Coleman, author of a considerable body of work, including nearly 150 articles and some twenty books, including The Adolescent Society (1961); the famous “Coleman Report” on equal opportunity in American schools, which was the basis for the federal policy of racial desegregation of schools (Coleman et al., 1966); The Mathematics of Collective Action (1973); Power and the Structure of Society (1974b); The Asymmetric Society (1982); and, most recently, Public and Private High Schools: The Impact of Communities (Coleman and Hoffer 1986).
-
[26]
Because of the institutional and intellectual gap between theory and practice in the United States, and in particular the representation of the former as an autonomous “specialty” essentially of pure conceptual exegesis (as reflected in the indigenous term theorizing). Parsons remains, against all odds, the cardinal reference in the American sociological field for whoever wants to ensure the status of theoretical discourse to his subject. It is not surprising, therefore, that the fiftieth anniversary of the publication of his first book, The Structure of Social Action, in 1937, was celebrated with great pomp and circumstance at the annual conference of the American Sociological Association in 1987, The session was reminiscent of a totemic ritual in many ways and included Bernard Barber, Harold Garfinkel (both of whom were trained by Parsons at Harvard), Jeffrey Alexander (who is now trying to rekindle the flame, cf. Alexander 1988c) and Jonathan Turner.
-
[27]
It may seem paradoxical that Coleman should look to Parsons for the “promising beginnings” of the utilitarian theory of action that he intends to develop, since we know that the voluntarism that the Harvard master placed at the epicenter of his sociology is defined precisely by an irreducible opposition to utilitarianism. The fact that Coleman does not note this antinomy, or rather, gives it as a continuity by confusing Parsons’ voluntarism with Benthamian purposiveness, strongly suggests the tactical character of the discursive reference to Parsons (even if unconsciously so). This paradox, while only apparent, is reminiscent of the strategy of legitimization employed by Parsons himself half a century earlier in his interpretation of Durkheim and Weber, which, we recall, consisted, by means of a fictitious retro-projection, in presenting his own theory as the systematization that makes explicit an “involuntary and unnoticed” convergence between them and advances towards a normative conception of action, which resolves the eternal Hobbesian problem of social order.
-
[28]
Amartya K. Sen (1977) offers a succinct exposition and stimulating critique of these anthropological presuppositions in his article “Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economies.”
-
[29]
Coleman (1986a, p. 1312; 1986b, p. 347 and p. 360-363). French readers will easily recognize the problematic of ‘methodological individualism’, e.g. Boudon (1979, see postscript) and Padioleau (1986), even if the latter struggles to distinguish the French version of the RAT from its American by shamelessly – and somewhat ungraciously – calling the latter ‘rustic utilitarianism’ (p. 210).
-
[30]
In a paper presented at an economics and management conference on the inadequacies of the utilitarian model of action (and published in the Journal of Business under the title “Psychological Structure and Social Structure in Economic Models”, 1986d), Coleman urges participants to focus on the micro-macro step rather than wasting their time complexifying the “micro-foundations of purposive action”: “It is the defects in the apparatus which effects the transition from the level of the individual actor to that of the system’s behavior which lays the most hope for progress” for economic theory, not the revision of the scheme of rational action which underlies it. See also his plenary lecture at the Annual Conference of the American Economic Association, “Introducing Social Structure into Economic Analysis” (Coleman, 1984): “It is not by abandoning the conception of rational action of individuals” that social science will be advanced “but by modifying the organizational assumptions that translate individual action into collective or systemic action.”
-
[31]
In an earlier paper (“Microfoundations and Macrosocial Theory”), Coleman (1986b) proposes a slightly different typology of aggregation mechanisms that includes, in addition to markets, authoritarian organizations, and norms, social choice rules (e.g. electoral systems) and collective behaviors (e.g. panics or rumors).
-
[32]
See his articles “Social Structure and the Emergence of Norms Among Rational Actors”, and “Norms as Social Capital” (Coleman, 1986e; 1987c).
-
[33]
For various graphical variants of this basic scheme, see Coleman (1987b). The example reproduced here is meant to model Weber’s thesis in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.
-
[34]
Cf. his reinvention of the concept of social capital in Social Capital in the Creation of Human Capital (Coleman, 1988a), and the article “Free Riders and Zealots: The Role of Social Networks” (Coleman, 1988b).
-
[35]
To extend it, one can read with great profit the work of Stanley Lieberson (1985), in which one of the major practitioners of the canonical methods of multivariate analysis subjects it to a piercing methodological critique, which was the subject of a very instructive debate in the 1987 volume of Sociological Methodology.
-
[36]
William H. Sewell Jr. (not to be confused with his father William H. Sewell, an ultra-quantitative sociologist of the Wisconsin School who was one of the initiators of status attainment research, and whose influence continues to be felt long after his retirement, since his protégé and heir, Aage Soerensen, was recently entrusted with the direction of the sociology department of Harvard University in desperate search of hard legitimacy: On Sewell Sr’s career, read Sewell, 1988) is first and foremost an excellent specialist in French social history. His doctoral dissertation in history at the University of California at Berkeley in 1971 was on “The Structure of the Working Class in Marseilles in the Mid-19th Century” and was published as The Men and Women of Marseilles. 1820-1870 (Sewell, 1985a). William H. Sewell Jr. now holds the prestigious joint chair of sociology and history vacated by Charles Tilly at the University of Michigan in Ann Arbor. Among his most important publications are Social Change and the Rise of Working-Class Politics in Nineteenth-Century Marseilles (Sewell, 1974a); Etat, Corps, and Ordre: Some Notes on the Social Vocabulary of the French Old Regime (1974b); Corporations Republicaines: The Revolutionary Idiom of Parisian Workers in 1848 (1979); Work and Revolution in France: The Language of Labor from the Old Régime to 1848 (1980); La confraternité des prolétaires : conscience de classe sous la monarchie de Juillet (1981); Artisans, Factory Workers, and the Formation of the French Working Class, 1789-1848 (1986); and Uneven Development, the Autonomy of Politics, and the Dockworkers of Nineteenth-Century Marseilles (1988).
-
[37]
Collins (1986a, p. 1346). See Calhoun (1987) for a comparison with England, where there is a similar flowering of historical sociology (evidenced by the recent launch of the journal Historical Sociology), but mainly under the leadership of historians, and Sztompka’s (1986) remarks in “The Renaissance of Historical Orientation in Sociology.”
-
[38]
Portes (1976) provides an excellent overview of the subfield of macro developmental sociology around this time.
-
[39]
Among others, W. J. Wilson (1980), Lieberson (1980), and Morawska (1985) on ethnic and racial relations; on the state, the book edited by Rueschemeyer, Evans, and Skocpol (1985) marks the ascendancy of the neoinstitutionalist approach (or “state-centered theories” as opposed to “society-centered theories”); also Poggi (1978), Quadagno (1988), Weir, Orloff and Skocpol (1988). Progress in this area of research can be followed via the quarterly States and Social Structures Newsletter published by the Social Science Research Council in New York.
-
[40]
On Anglo-American work in the historical sociology of class, see Roy’s (1984) useful synopsis. Some of the more prominent recent works include Sabel (1984), Burawoy (1985), Katznelson (1981), Katnelson and Zolberg (1986), Moore (1978), Aminzade (1981), Calhoun (1982), Wilentz (1984), Levine (1984), McNall (1988), and Haydu (1988).
-
[41]
Tilly, Tilly and Tilly (1975), Paige (1975), Trimberger (1978), Skocpol (1979), Bonnell (1983), Hunt (1984), Traugott (1985), Tilly (1985), and Burke (1988).
-
[42]
Notably Sarfatti-Larson (1977), Starr (1982), Geison (1984), Rueschemeyer (1973; 1986).
-
[43]
Wallerstein (1974; 1979; 1984), Hechter (1975), Chirot (1976), Block (1977), Evans (1978), Mann (1986), Hall (1985), see Wallerstein (1987) and Chirot and Hall (1982), respectively, for a synthetic presentation and a review of the so-called “world-system” theory, as well as the annual “Political Economy of the World System” series published by Sage under Wallerstein’s direction.
-
[44]
In cultural-historical sociology, we may mention, to limit ourselves to the principal works of the recent period, Zelizer (1985), Zaret (1986), Griswold (1986), Laitin (1986), Hunt (1984), Patterson (1984), Corrigan and Sayer (1985), Abercrombie et al., (1980), Sennett (1977), and historian Herbert G. Gutman’s remarkable posthumous collection of essays, Power and Culture (1987).
-
[45]
Notably Hall and Jefferson (1976), Hebdige (1979), and Willis (1977), widely cited and used, especially in teaching.
-
[46]
The influence of Geertz’s semiological conception of culture (e.g. 1974) on Sewell dates from their common stay at the University of Chicago in the early 1970s. Later, Sewell spent several years at the Center for Advanced Studies in Princeton at the invitation of the latter. On the impact of Geertz’s symbolic anthropology on historical research in America, see Walters (1980); also Darnton (1984, p. 9-13 and p. 296-303), and Bourdieu, Chartier and Darnton (1985). A critical discussion of the thorny methodological and theoretical problems posed by Geertzian thick description can be found in Roseberry (1982), Shankman (1984), Crapanzano (1986), and in Schneider’s (1987) insightful article, “Culture-as-Text in the Work of Clifford Geertz.” On the interpretive current more generally, Rabinow and Sullivan (1979).
-
[47]
This is one of the theses that Goffman (1974) develops in his critique of interactionism and ethnomethodology with the notion of “framework-analysis”.
-
[48]
Sewell (1987, p. 168). For Albert Hirschman (1982, p. 79), “a more general criticism that can be levelled at Olson’s analysis – and at much of economic decision theory in general – is that the subjects, while effective and often ingenious and tortuous, are devoid of history.” Timothy Luke (1985, p. 70), a reasoned proponent of RAT, agrees that it logically presupposes “uneducated, unhistoricized, depoliticized and unsocialized” individuals. Adam Przeworski (1985a, p. 381) himself recognizes that “the ontological assumptions of the rational choice model – and especially the assumption of undifferentiated, unchanging and unrelated ‘individuals’ – are untenable.”
-
[49]
As demonstrated, among others, by Elias (1973), Abercrombie et al., Foucault (1975; 1976), Rosaldo (1980), Carrithers, Collins and Lukes (1985).
-
[50]
Sewell (1987, p. 169, note 2). Anthony Giddens (1977) has established that, in any case, the Hobbesian problem never occupied the central place in the thought of the founding fathers that it does in orthodox American theory. We know, moreover, since C. B. Macpherson’s classic study, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (1962) that the political and social presuppositions of the Hobbesian vision of the social order are more related to the economic and social organization of English mercantilism of the 17th century than to a hypothetical “state of nature.”
-
[51]
His reaction is to be compared with the harsh criticisms he formulates elsewhere against the interactionist approach of Gusfield and the comparative method employed by Skocpol and Orloff (Coleman, 1986b).
-
[52]
See Van Parijs (1981b) for a summary of these distinctions.
-
[53]
Van Parijs (1981b, p. 312). Here Russell Hardin goes so far as to conclude, in his article “Difficulties with the Notion of Economic Rationality” (1983, p. 465), that “The individual rationality supposedly at the root of economic explanations at the societal level is essentially a chimera.” Similarly. Douglas (1986, p. 102) concedes that while individuals make decisions, it is institutions that define the classifications between which they choose.
-
[54]
Hollis (1987). And one could quote Wittgenstein (1965), for whom “At the end of reasons comes persuasion.”
-
[55]
Winch (1958). The main moments of this long controversy which continues to this day are gathered in the two volumes edited by Wilson (1970) and Hollis and Lukes (1982). On Rationalitätstreit in the philosophy of science, one can read with profit the original work of Paul A. Roth, Meaning and Method in the Social Sciences: A Case for Methodological Pluralism (1987).
-
[56]
Gilligan (1982) and Benhabib and Cornell (1987) and the immense literature that has developed at an exponential rate in recent years at the intersection of critical theory, feminism, and historiography, from which Joan Scott’s recent book Gender and the Politics of History (1988) stands out.
-
[57]
M. Burawoy, “Mythological Individualism”, lecture delivered at Harvard University in May 1988 on the occasion of a Symposium in honor of Parsons.
-
[58]
According to a study by Nobel Prize winner Wassily Leontief (reported by Hirsch et al., 1987, p. 330-31), more than half of the articles published in the American Economic Review between 1977 and 1981 relied on pure mathematical models without containing any observational data, while less than 0,5% of the authors had made the effort to produce new data. To Coleman’s credit, however, there is no such disproportion between theoretical effort and empirical observation, in contrast to the Analytical Marxists (except Przeworski and Wright), who, to say the least, do not bother with observational data. This is in violation of the principles laid down by Marx who recommended, in The German Ideology: “Empirical observation must in each separate instance bring out empirically and without any mystification and speculation, the connection of the social and political structure with production. The social structure and the State are continually evolving out of the life-process of definite individuals, but of individuals, not as they appear in their own or other people’s imagination, but as they really are: i.e., as they operate, produce materially, and hence as they work under definite material limits, presuppositions and conditions independent of their will” (Marx and Engels, 1970, p. 46-47, emphasis added).
-
[59]
See Hirschman (1986, chapter 4), Sen (1977), Lieberstein (1976; 1979, especially p. 493-496 on the problems posed by the maximization postulate), Sen and Williams (1982), and Miller and Williams (1982). According to Spiro Latsis (1972), the “research program” of neoclassical microeconomics has been in a phase of degeneration for quite some time.
-
[60]
“Rational choice theory may well be nothing more than an ‘ideology’ that merely transcribes into the more acceptable theoretical language of the individual market decision the harsh reality of managerially imposed decisions” (Luke, 1985, p. 77).
-
[61]
Lash and Urry (1984) make it clear that Elster’s postulate of individualism and game theory are an ontology of the social, not simply a methodology. The function of political denial of the RAT has been brilliantly noted by Albert Hirschman (1982, p. 78-79): “Now it must be recalled that Mancur Olson proclaimed the impossibility of collective action (just as Daniel Bell proclaimed the ‘end of ideology’) at the precise moment when the Western world was about to be all but engulfed by an unprecedented wave of public movements. […] It seems to me paradoxically conceivable that the success of Olson’s book owes something to its having been contradicted by the subsequently evolving events. Once the latter had safely run their course, the many people who found them deeply upsetting could go back to The Logic of Collective Action and find in it good and reassuring reasons why those collective actions of the sixties should never have happened in the first place, were perhaps less real than they seemed and would be most unlikely to recur. Thus the book did not suffer from being contradicted by subsequent events; rather, it gained by actively contradicting them and became a great success among those who found these events intolerable and totally aberrant.” It is to this function of derealization of the social that the normative, even prescriptive dimension of the RAT responds, noted or claimed by many authors, like Luke (1985, p. 98), Downs (for whom the political RAT “occupies a twilight zone between normative models and prescriptive models,” 1957, p. 31) and Van Parijs (1981a, p. 305). Gibson (1977) goes so far as to argue that no non-normative conception of rationality is philosophically tenable.
-
[62]
For example, Boudon (1984), but also Jon Elster (1979), who sees Morgenstern and Weber as the two masters of rational theory.
-
[63]
Weber (1978, p. 6-7). On the multiple meanings of the concepts of rationality and rationalization in Weber, see Brubaker (1984) and Sica (1988), who has recently subjected Weber’s bias in favor of rationality to close scrutiny. This Weberian distinction between model and reality finds a fruitful extension in Alfred Schutz’s (1953; 1970, p. 125-159) opposition between “scientific rationality” and “common sense rationality,” an opposition taken up and elaborated empirically by Garfinkel and the ethnomethodologists, whose breaching experiments (Garfinkel, 1967, p. 35-75) demonstrate better than all the speeches that social life would simply be intolerable and impossible if social agents actually behaved in the manner of rational actors of the RAT.
1The exchange in the American Journal of Sociology [2] between the neoclassical economics-inspired sociologist James S. Coleman on the one hand, and the historian-sociologist William H. Sewell, Jr., influenced by Geertz’s cultural anthropology, on the other, is an opportunity to take note of the rise, or the return to prominence, of two influential currents in the American sociological field: the theory of “rational action” (Rational Action Theory, or RAT) and historical and cultural sociology. Beyond the men, two epistemological poles and two conceptions of social action and science are, in fact, in conflict.
Coleman and the offensive of homo economicus
2The RAT that Coleman calls for in his manifesto article does not, strictly speaking, constitute an original theoretical movement in the American social sciences, but rather an enlarged and modernized application of the “economic approach” to social phenomena, whose historical roots go back to the individualistic philosophy of Anglo-Saxon utilitarianism, [3] and whose founding postulate was stated by Gary Becker (1976, p. 14) as follows:
“All human behavior can be conceived as involving participants who maximize their utility from a stable set of preferences and who accumulate the optimal amount of information and other inputs in a variety of markets.”
4Under the various names of rational choice, [4] the problem of collective action, [5] the search for “microfoundations” [6] or methodological individualism, this approach is currently enjoying an unprecedented popularity in the United States, which can be explained by the conjunction of several factors.
5The first factor is the “microsociological” or “constructivist” revolt that put an end to the functionalist hegemony in the 1960s. The paradigmatic breakdown of American sociology that followed authorized a return to the actor, which, if it was mainly carried out in the “interpretative” or cognitive mode, with the symbolic interactionism of Blumer and Goffman, the ethnomethodology of Garfinkel and Cicourel, phenomenological sociology inspired by Schutz and conversation analysis of Sacks and Schegloff, [7] also includes an “instrumentalist” or rational variant represented by the behaviorism of George Caspar Homans and the exchange theory of Peter Blau. This shift in the center of gravity of the sociological field towards the subjectivity pole is combined today with a clear revival of interest in theory – even in “Grand Theory” – so as to create particularly favorable conditions for the propagation of RAT, in which it is not forbidden to discern a sort of return of the repressed utilitarian sociology that had gradually dissipated over the course of the 1970s. [8]
6The second factor is a full-scale attack on the sociological citadel by economists and their allies from within. Adam Przeworksi observes that :
“The social sciences are today being attacked by an offensive without precedent since the 1890s: a deliberate push to impose the monopoly of the economic method on any study of society. […] And this offensive has been largely victorious.” [9]
8Without going so far as to share this self-interested and somewhat hasty diagnosis of the outcome of the battle, one can only agree in noting the rapid proliferation of economic models in American social science [10]. This is the case in particular in the sociology of organizations, where the work of economists has been at the origin of important developments, such as the transaction cost approach or the theory of “principal-agent” relationships, [11] but also in the study of social movements, the family and the school, as in the scattered body of research and analytical techniques gathered under the label of network theory. [12] Admittedly, there are relatively few avowed disciples of RAT among sociologists – in contrast to political scientists – and the intrusion of the economic method into the field of sociology has not happened without triggering a vigorous counter-attack. Thus the neo-classical concept of the market is today, if not discredited, at least strongly contested by the work of Granovetter, Powell and White, and the rapid rise of economic sociology in recent years suggests that the sociological questioning of the notions of orthodox economics is only just beginning. [13]
9The fact remains that, reinforced by the social philosophy of “voluntaristic individualism” which, since the beginning, has permeated American sociology, and by the instrumental positivism which makes the successes – social if not scientific – of neo-classical economics the model of scientificity, [14] the scheme of rational action now underlies, even if implicitly, a good number of apparently atheoretical research sectors. In any case, the economist offensive is sufficiently threatening for some sociologists to be moved by it and to warn their colleagues of the dangers of giving in too easily to a fusion of sister disciplines under the aegis of the reductive concept of rational choice: sociology would have nothing to gain by trading its sense of the variety and complexity of reality for the “unrealistic neatness” of economic models. [15]
10Two examples of this epistemological arrogance of economists: At a symposium on Paradigms in the Social Sciences held in 1986 on the campus of the University of Chicago – a stronghold of RAT if ever there was one [16] – the Nobel Prize-winning economist James Buchanan did not hesitate to proclaim that (quoted by Hirsch et al., 1987, p. 317):
“Those who prefer to conduct research on class relations, states and organizations as such without taking the trouble to reduce the analysis to the behavior of the individuals who participate in them do not, in my opinion, deserve the title of social scientist, if the term is to have any meaning at all.”
12In a conference on sociological theory at the University of Chicago in 1983, his colleague Mancur Olson responded to Joseph Gusfield, who had just defended interpretive sociology (“humanistic science”) at the end of a paper on the social construction of the notion of a public problem such as drinking and driving, with these words (Olson, in Lindenberg, Coleman and Nowak, 1986, p. 202):
14On the side of sociologists, Michael Hechter’s book Principles of Group Solidaritv offers an archetypal example of this creeping economism that dares not say its name. Having, after a summary trial, condemned without appeal the “normativist, structuralist and functionalist” approaches (1987, p. 20-29), simplified at will for the occasion, this former follower of neo-Marxist theory (he was, at other times, one of the most prominent disciples of Immanuel Wallerstein at the University of Columbia), freshly converted to the RAT, proposes to replace them with a rational theory of group cohesion. This theory is articulated around three basic elements which immediately give an idea of the conceptual impoverishment produced by such a conversion: individuals “bearers of a set of discrete, unambiguous, and transitive preferences”; institutions, i.e. “sets of rules which effectively constrain individual behavior in various ways”; and “collective products” resulting from the combination of individual behaviors (p. 30-31). Question: why do individuals believe in or join groups? Answer: in order to be able to consume the exclusive and immanent goods that these alone are able to produce. At the end of a close examination of several cases, parliamentary groups, credit associations, internal labor markets of firms and communes (a very particular sample since it contains only formal elective groups. What about all the collectives where membership does not come from the logic of deliberate and conscious individual choice, families, clans, classes, nations, racial or ethnic communities, sexual groups or age groups?), the author arrives at this remarkable discovery full of utilitarian common sense: a group is all the more solidary the more its members depend on it and the more its capacities of formal control and sanction are extended.
15In conclusion, Hechter agrees that RAT suffers from some alarming shortcomings: it is unable to explain why one type of group emerges rather than another in order to quench the same unquenchable thirst for ‘immanent collective goods’ that endlessly torments maximizing individuals; it denies any role to collective identities and feelings; it proves incapable of shedding light on the dynamics of institutional development and the outbursts of collective action that occur in the apparent absence of any formal mechanism of control or retribution; and lastly, and above all, it remains totally silent on the causal variable which, supposedly, controls the whole model, namely the formation of individual preferences (p. 183-184). This does not, however, prevent him from asserting without further formality that “far from being immiscible, sociology and rational choice are mutually complementary… Together, [they] offer today the best hope of merging the individual and structural levels of analysis into a coherent whole capable of producing falsifiable empirical propositions” (p. 8 and p. 186).
16Finally, although rooted in a fundamentally conservative individualistic social philosophy, and even organically linked to a form of libertarian capitalism which would seem, at first sight, to make it antithetical to a critical social science, the theoretical claims of sociological RAT have been considerably reinforced on the left by the parallel emergence of Analytical Marxism (also known as game-theoretic Marxism or rational choice Marxism). This new school of thought, whose hard core consists of the philosophers Gerald Cohen and Jon Elster, the political scientists Adam Przeworski and Robert Van Parijs, the economist John Roemer and the (only) sociologist Erik Olin Wright (and to the periphery of which one can attach the philosophers Andrew Levine and Allen Wood, historian Robert Brenner and Norman Geras) aims to take up the problems of Marxism using the methodology of neo-classical economics. He does it on the basis of a philosophy of action – in fact a real social ontology related to that which founds Sartrian subjectivism [17] – which makes the structure of social relations the product of the composite and unintentional aggregation of the deliberate choices of individuals maximizing their interests during strategic interactions aiming for the efficient distribution of limited resources. [18]
17This heterogeneous and small (but extraordinarily active and cohesive, and therefore very visible) network that claims to be a hybrid between Marx and John Stuart Mill has forged the project of finally giving Marxism the logical and rational (to say the least: scientific in a sense that the Vienna Circle would not deny) foundations that, a century after the death of the author of Capital, it still lacks. [19] Its members distinguish themselves from their predecessors, notably the structuralists, of whom some are repentant defectors, by the fact that they apply without any qualms “the most advanced methods of analytic philosophy and ‘positivist’ social science” [20] to the traditional problems of Marxism – theory of history, exploitation, class conflicts, transition to socialism. That is essentially the theory of games, mathematical modeling and the concepts of equilibrium and market of neo-classical economics. One of its principal spokesmen does not hesitate to go so far as to set up analytical philosophy as a sine qua non of the scientific method. [21]
18This “marginalist historical materialism”, if we may be allowed to use an expression that borders on conceptual barbarism, thus agrees with the sociological RAT in making the rational choice of the individual the Archimedean point of social theory. Indeed, Analytical Marxism is in every respect the counterpart, in the sub-field of “professorial Marxism,” [22] of Coleman’s rational choice theory in the sub-field of orthodox sociology. Just as Colemanian RAT cannot be understood outside of its oppositional relationship to functionalism and its hypersocialized conception of action which, in the Parsonian scheme, makes the agent the passive servant of all-powerful consensual cultural norms (Wrong, 1961), so in the same way the rationalist and intentionalist hypersubjectivism of Analytical Marxism is defined in a reaction to the exacerbated anti-humanism of Althusserian Marxism for which the agent is reduced to the rank of support of reified and quasi-anthropomorphized structures, continuously interpellated by ideological apparatuses with infinite mystifying capacities.
19The RAT current is not yet sufficiently widespread, nor sufficiently homogeneous, to claim a large audience among sociologists as a theory, [23] and it is too early to predict whether it will continue to spread or, on the contrary, enter a phase of decline – as certain precursory signs lead us to suppose. [24]
20It is in this triple context – resurgence of microsociology and theory (including the micro-macro debate), invasion of economic models and invention of Analytical Marxism – that Coleman’s article is set. A true proclamation of a “theoretical state of emergency” in favor of utilitarian individualism, [25] it illustrates in a paradigmatic way this forceful introduction of the homo economicus in the heart of the American sociological field. However, the Chicago sociologist is not content with simply repeating the postulates of economic analysis: he strives to give the RAT a noble theoretical filiation by linking it to the Parsonsian work, even if it means a dubious reinterpretation of the history of sociological thought in the United States; he makes an original diagnosis of the origins of the growing divorce between theory and empiricism; finally, he suggests several ways of enriching and making the economic model more complex by introducing the missing notion of social structure in various forms.
21Coleman’s first objective is to give utilitarian individualism the titles of sociological nobility which, since Durkheim, it has sorely lacked by recreating an intellectual genealogy that links it to that totemic figure of theory that is, inevitably, Talcott Parsons. [26] His plea for RAT thus opens with a historical reminder of the disappointed promises of American sociological theory: if the scientific program announced in 1937 by Parsons in The Structure of Social Action did contain the premises of a “voluntarist” theory of action, [27] neither he, nor his epigones, nor his rivals were able to bring them to fruition. Unable to link the subjective aims of the individual and institutions, Parsons himself very quickly took refuge in the study of the social system and its preconditions. George Homans, for his part, went in the opposite direction and, completely losing sight of social structure and intentionality, came to reduce the sociology of action to a behaviorist analysis of exchange à la Skinner; Merton, finally, if he partially absolved functionalism of the original sin of teleology, did not succeed in giving social action those rational “microfoundations” which it lacked.
22From this theoretical deficiency was born a growing schism between theory and empiricism. For at the moment when the individual – or more precisely the notion of deliberate choice as a modus operandi of individual practices, which Coleman holds, as we shall see, to be consubstantial to a theory of action – disappears, more or less, from theory, empirical research makes it its new unit of observation. The revolution in techniques of observation and statistical analysis which took place in the immediate post-war period, and which saw sample surveys based on individuals abstracted from their social and cultural contexts supplant community studies (in the style of Lynds’ Middletown), led research in a direction diametrically opposed to that taken at the theoretical level by both the functionalists and their rivals of the so-called “conflict school.” This type of research has two shortcomings from the point of view of the sociological theory that Coleman advocates: although individualistic, surveying research uses a causal and behaviorist mode of explanation and not a strategic and intentional one; it is therefore incapable of tracing the individual to the “behavior” of the social system. In addition to this accelerated development of statistical techniques, reinforced by the whole demographic tradition which reduces the analysis of social causality to a simple manipulation of mathematical indices, an objective change in the social structure has aggravated this divergence between theory and empiricism. Under the effect of the exponential growth of markets, mass media, large companies and bureaucracies, the principle of structuring the social has shifted from the local community to the national society. This transformation of social relations has itself determined a mutation of the social demand for social science, hence the rise of market studies and policy research (cf. Coleman, 1978) which have accentuated the individualistic and causal bias (in the sense of statistical causality) of research and hindered the elaboration of the rational foundations of sociological theory.
23In order to remedy this growing divorce between an empiricism centred on an abstract individual devoid of intentions and a theory which operates exclusively at the level of a system artificially endowed with its own ends, Coleman proposes to restore the telos to the individual and to import into sociology the anthropological principles which underlie neo-classical microeconomics. [28] Once the ends that functionalists wrongly attribute to the social system have been repatriated to the level of the rational actor, sociological theory can be reduced to the elucidation of two puzzles: first, how do the intentional behaviors of actors combine to produce systemic consequences? Second, how do these economically goal-oriented actions in turn become shaped by the constraints resulting from the functioning of this system? [29] But by focusing the theoretical gaze on the combination of autonomous individual behaviors into collective outcomes, Coleman presupposes that the question of the nature and immanent logic of social behaviors has been resolved. In other words, and this is a major paradox, the unthinking adoption of the philosophy of utilitarian subjectivism prevents Coleman’s theory of action from posing as a problem the very thing that is supposed to constitute its object.
24It is striking to what extent Coleman takes the subjectivist philosophy of rational action, conceived as a reflexive sequence of conscious decisions by an economic actor who is economically and socially unconditioned, as a self-evident datum brutum that does not require the slightest proof. Thus, he opens his collection of articles Individual Interests and Collective Action (1986c, p. 1) with this statement held to be established sub specie aeternitatis:
“The rational action of individuals has a unique attraction for sociological theory. One can say that one has ‘explained’ a social institution or process if and only if one has accounted for it on the basis of the rational action of individuals. The very concept of rational action is a conception of action that is ‘understandable’ […], an action about which no further questions arise. Thus social theory can take the purposive goal-oriented individual as its starting point, although psychology may wish to explore this system in order to discover what makes his action coherent or ‘purposeful’.” [30]
26This statement can be compared with that of John Roemer, for whom the assumption of individual rationality is also in the realm of self-evidence: “Methodological individualism is a deductive method which attempts to derive historical observations from basic assumptions about individual behavior which are sufficiently fundamental to be taken as self-evident” (Roemer 1982b, p. 253). Or the philosophic anthropology underlying Jon Elster’s Making Sense of Marx, which Barry Hindess (1986, p. 442) noted in a recent review as “effectively introducing methodological individualism as a premise that requires no defense.”
27And it is only because he has accepted as fully proven (taken for granted) the utilitarian and individualistic philosophy that constitutes the anthropological unconscious of liberal economics, and assumes the question of the logic of social action to be resolved, that Coleman (1986b, p. 362-363) can assert that:
“The main theoretical challenge [faced by sociology] is to show how individual actions combine to produce a social product… There must be social institutions in reality (such as the market or electoral systems) which translate individual tastes and endowments into a set of prices and a distribution of goods or into a collective decision. What is needed in social theory is a conceptual apparatus to describe this translation.”
“The central intellectual problem of the social sciences […] is this: we understand and can model individual behavior, but we are rarely able to make an appropriate transition from that level to the behavior of the system formed by those same individuals.”
30Elsewhere he continues: “The most successful example of modeling this transition is the pure and perfect market model of neo-classical economic theory” (Coleman, 1987b, p. 157-58). Or (Coleman, 1986b, p. 364):
“I believe that the appropriate paradigm for sociology is one derived from Walrasian equilibrium theory, although it differs in part in that not all social goods are divisible, without external effects, and do not all obey the conservation principle; and in part because of the social structure that a Walrasian system ignores.”
32As a result (Coleman in Lindenberg et al., 1986, p. 124):
“It seems to me that sociology could take one aspect of microeconomic theory, namely the behavioral model of rational choice, and add to the market a variety of other structures through which social products are generated.”
34According to Coleman, the transition from the micro to the macro can take place, not through the market alone, as postulated in Gary Becker’s relatively crude economic models, but through three main types of mechanisms: markets, hierarchies or systems of authority relations or contractual relationships, and normative systems. He also mentioned the role of trust and communication networks. [31] All of them, however, are indebted to the same analysis in terms of individual interest. There is not a single norm that the Chicago sociologist does not try to explain as the result of the rational action of agents seeking to effectively regulate the behaviour of third parties whose ‘negative side effects’ they have to suffer. [32] The figure opposite illustrates the structure that any sociological theory must therefore adopt, the heart of the latter being formed, in Coleman’s eyes, by the type 3 relation, going back from the micro to the macro, the type 4 relations (macro-macro) being the epitome of fallacious reasoning in sociology. [33]
Basic structure of sociological theory according to Coleman
Basic structure of sociological theory according to Coleman
35James Coleman’s merit here is to go beyond the ultra-simplistic hypotheses of a Becker by recognizing the existence of micro-macro “translation” mechanisms other than the simple market. By clearly stating the need to link the “theory of action”, even if it is rational, to a theory of social structure, [34] Coleman also avoids some of the aporias that undermine Elster’s approach, for whom structure is reduced to a set of games (the prisoner’s dilemma, the battle of the sexes, the insurance game, the loan for a loan, etc.), that is to say, in the final analysis, a series of individual interactions planned under ex ante specified constraints. Finally, his diagnosis of the yawning chasm between theory and empirical research contains an implicit critique of the methodological fetishism of orthodox American sociology, which seems salutary to us. [35] But these contributions are only possible against a background of unanalyzed premises and a truncated anthropology whose prohibitive costs Sewell will hasten to expose.
Sewell and the “golden age” of historical sociology in America
36That it is a trained historian and not a “pure” sociologist [36] answering Coleman’s question is not surprising if we know that historical and comparative sociology has been expanding in the United States for the last fifteen years. Observers as different as the behaviorist George Caspar Homans (1986) and the Weberian Randall Collins agree in seeing in it one of the most promising recent advances in social science on the other side of the Atlantic, the latter not hesitating, in his assessment of current trends in American sociology, to call it a veritable “golden age.” [37]
37This resurgence of historical sociology has its origins in the discredit, both scientific and political, that the societal transformations of the post-war period and the socio-political conflicts of the 1960s have inflicted on the theories of modernization (the psychology of Inkeles, McLelland, and Lerner, or the structuralism of Marion Levy and Walt W. Rostow) and to the functionalist evolutionism of Parsons and Eisenstadt, which until then had reigned unchallenged in Anglo-American macrosociology. [38] Encouraged by the rehabilitation of the classical tradition of Marx, Weber and Tocqueville, a new generation of young researchers found in the historical and comparative method the means not only to neutralize, by making them visible, the ideological and ethnocentric biases of the discipline, but also to escape from the sterile opposition of the historical and comparative method.
38It also avoided the sterile opposition of “Grand Theory” and “abstract empiricism” denounced by C. Wright Mills (1977), and followed in the wake of the pioneering work of Barrington Moore, Reinhard Bendix, Charles Tilly, Gerhard Lenski and Immanuel Wallerstein.
39Since then, historical sociology has extended to an ever larger and more varied universe of objects: From ethnic relations to the emergence of welfare states and their social policies, [39] through the formation of the working classes, [40] revolutions and popular insurrections, [41] the professions, [42] the history of power or the world capitalist system, [43] and more recently, to culture, [44] there is no longer any part of social reality that is foreign to it, to the point that it is now asserting itself as one of the most intellectually dynamic sectors of American sociology (even if it remains socially less powerful than the RAT).
40[…]
41The popularity of the cultural approach in historical sociology is a function of the recent expansion of cultural sociology (marked by the creation in 1987 of a section of Sociology of Culture within the ASA), among others under the impulse of Foucault, Elias, Bourdieu, Habermas, and the work of the Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies of the University of Birmingham, [45] and where one finds a connection similar to that between RAT and historical sociology, between institutionalist approaches which tend towards an instrumental view of action on the one hand and the sociology of culture on the other.
42This series of homothetic oppositions between rationality and norms, institution and agent, system and actor, structure and culture, impersonal cause and subjective meaning, is reproduced within historical macrosociology itself, within which, from this point of view, one can roughly distinguish two tendencies: one is structural and is partly linked to the current of American structuralism (associated with the names of Blau, Mayhew, Harrison White, Ron Burt, etc.), while the other is rather “culturalist,” and betrays the impact of Geertz [46] and of the symbolic anthropology born in Chicago in the 1960s, as well as the persistent influence of the hermeneutic and interactionist tradition.
43[…]
44It is this culturalist interpretation of the historical method that informs Sewell’s criticisms and counter-proposals in his response to Coleman. Against the abstractions of the individualist scheme of rational choice, Sewell outlines a theory of action attentive to the concrete spatial and temporal localization of the processes studied, centered on the dialectical interplay of meaningful actions and their structural contexts, and imbued with a concern for historical variation and specificity. Sewell underlines the simplifying and unilateral character of Coleman’s model and questions the distinction between the micro and macro levels of analysis that is at its core. His critique focuses on each of the three main types of relationships identified by Coleman, and especially on the exorbitant importance that Coleman gives to the micro-macro relation.
45Sewell argues first of all that the micro-micro relation (type 1 on the diagram above), which Coleman tends to present as self-evident, can neither be grasped nor even conceptualized without first giving oneself the macro-sociological framework which alone defines and determines it, and that therefore, in all rigor, it only makes sense as a direct and inescapable function of the totality of the type 2 and 3 relations from which Coleman extracts it by means of a theoretical coup de force. In other words, the relations between individual behaviors pass through the complete system of relevant social relations and are not amenable to an individualistic analysis. [47] In the same vein, Sewell notes that Coleman’s RAT is based on a Hobbesian conception of the individual as an autonomous entity outside of history and society, and assumes that “the interests, preferences, or goals of individuals can be deduced without difficulty from their social or economic position.” [48] Drawing on the work of Geertz, Therborn, Foucault, Bourdieu and Hochchild, he suggests, on the contrary, that it is not enough to posit ex cathedra the existence of individual interests, preferences and goals in order to elucidate the effects of the so-called “macro” level on the behavior of agents (a type 2 relation). For the individual and their values cannot be hypostasized and reduced to exogenous variables in this relationship. The social person is indeed constituted in and by the totality of the social and cultural links where the biological individual who is the “support” is inserted. Individuality is not ahistorical but results from precise sociohistorical processes. [49] And it is the history of these fields, such as it is specified through the filter of the individual and collective trajectory of the agents who invest in them, which defines the habitus as a generating system of preferences, that RAT declares, by methodological decree, to be exogenous to social action and structure. By omitting to ask the question of the social conditions of formation of these interests, preferences and goals, Coleman refrains from seeing the individual as a social and historical construction that is also subject to sociological analysis. From then on, he has no choice but to regress to the limited (and in many ways, it seems to us, narrowly Americano-centric) model of a homo economicus endlessly pursuing an abstract and unchanging interest.
46Finally, Sewell reminds us that the micro-macro transition (type 3 relationship), which according to Coleman constitutes what Lakatos would call the “hard core” of sociological theory, cannot be limited to the aggregation, whether by means of exchanges, hierarchies or normative constraints, of individual actions all uniformly oriented towards the maximization of an interest already constituted outside any historical and social context. In reality, agents never create a social system ex nihilo, and all theoretical edifices based on such Robinsonades, to speak as Marx, are doomed to produce conclusions as fictitious and unreal as their hypotheses. And Sewell aptly notes that the celebrated “Hobbesian problem of social order,” formulated by Parsons and by which American sociological theory has since bought itself a (false) philosophical conscience, is only a “pre-sociological or non-sociological” problem. [50]
47It is clear that, for Sewell, it is the very starting point of Coleman’s model that is problematic here: by postulating a presocial state of nature, the latter “reduces the problem of action in its dialectical reality – how structurally constituted actors act so that the combined effect of their actions transforms the very structures that constitute them – to the simpler, narrower, and far less interesting linear question of how, under varying conditions, the actions of individuals pursuing their own self-interest cumulate to produce various social consequences” (Sewell, 1987, p. 169). In place of this neo-Hobbesian problematic, Sewell outlines a sociological research program inspired by history and interpretive anthropology, anchored by the following assumptions:
481) The dispositions, practices and representations of agents are the product of specific cultural and historical conditions, not transhistorical data.
492) Every society contains within it conflicts and tensions leading to structural changes that generally differ from those deliberately pursued by the agents.
503) These systemic consequences, whether intentional or not, depend not only on the constellation of goals and resources of the parties involved, but also on their own temporal articulation.
514) Social agents are capable of reflexivity in that they tend to adjust their habits, desires, and worldviews to objective transformations.
52Sewell (1987, p. 171) closes his critique with a brief plea for a resolutely historical sociology:
“Instead of abandoning history for ‘as if’ stories, sociology would do better to strive for a more theoretically and empirically rigorous specification of the complex dialectical processes by which real social systems are transformed by historically dated and situated actors.”
54In his response to Sewell, Coleman (1987a) stands firm. [51] He does not want to see in Sewell’s criticisms anything more than the expression of a difference of “interest in knowledge,” as Habermas would say, between the sociologist, who would aim at establishing general relationships between variables, and the historian, who would seek to grasp phenomena or chains of particular events in a narrative mode. Taking refuge behind this perennial dichotomy between nomothetic and ideographic research Coleman merely reiterates what for him constitutes the two cardinal faults of all sociological theory: failing to descend to the level of individual actors and their (rational) conduct, and concentrating on the macro-micro articulation to the detriment of the opposite movement. It is true that to tackle the objections and questions raised by Sewell head-on would require him to question the implicit ontological and even metaphysical postulates of the rational choice scheme – in other words, to take the trouble to elaborate a real theory of social action instead of confining himself to a theory of the combination of rationally reconstructed individual behaviors.
Beyond the rationalist illusion of “mythological individualism”
55As we can see, the interest of this Coleman-Sewell debate goes far beyond the simple exchange between two authors, since it offers a paradigmatic confrontation between two epistemological poles whose force of attraction is growing today in the field of American social sciences and which can be quickly and simply characterized as follows: on the one hand, the individualist and rationalist pole, which conceives of the social order as the aggregation, simple or composite, of individual actions involving agents deliberately seeking to maximize their utility by the instrumental adjustment of available means to clearly given and ordered ends; and on the other hand, the historical and culturalist pole which endeavors to understand the logic of these same actions by piercing their subjective and contextual meaning, by discovering the logic of the constitution of the agents and their ends, and by tracing their reciprocal effects in time. On the one hand, there are formal models, most often mathematical, based on deliberately simplifying – sometimes grossly and unrealistically – postulates which form the basis of deductions of a predictive nature; on the other hand, there is an interpretative “reading” of reality as a ‘text’ which privileges induction and the comprehension of the meaning which the agent gives to their conduct. These are indeed two opposed conceptions of social action: homo rationalis vs. homo culturalis, or, in the language of Martin Hollis (1977), the Autonomous Man against the Plastic Man; hard science against soft science, Erklären against Verstehen, quantitative methods against qualitative procedures. And these two poles pull in opposite directions: while Coleman invites sociology to a rapprochement with economics, Sewell calls sociology to the side of anthropology and, in some ways, “anti-scientific” history.
56But did Sewell go far enough in his critique of the rationalist utilitarianism defended by Coleman? One is entitled to think not. Coleman appeals without further justification to the notion of rationality, a concept which is nowadays much debated within the camp of methodological rationalism. What kind of rationality does Coleman claim: Perfect or imperfect? Total (maximization) or selective (satisfaction)? Bayesian or non-Bayesian? Parametric or strategic? [52] So many questions to which he provides no answer. Nor does he answer the proven inability of RAT to explain the beliefs, preferences and cultural conventions that govern practices, [53] or the difficulty it has in not confusing preferences with reasons. [54]
57In order to circumscribe more precisely the field of validity of RAT, it is necessary and sufficient to recall the very thing that it must constantly repress in order to maintain its claims to paradigmatic hegemony, that is to say its social and economic conditions of possibility. The usefulness of the theory of rational choice depends on the degree to which its starting hypotheses are actually realized in practice. The most important of these assumptions is that the relevant forces are individuals with pre-existing interests or preferences that are coherent, hierarchical, transitive, unambiguous and not subject to intersubjective variation. From this postulate follows a second one, according to which individual behaviors are rational, i.e. efficiently oriented towards the satisfaction of the agent’s interests, which supposes that the agent has enough information to proceed to an intelligent choice (this premise of rationality can of course be diluted at will by resorting to the notion of “revealed preference,” which has the considerable advantage of rendering the demonstrations of the RAT entirely tautological). These postulates make the scheme of rational action particularly applicable in social contexts where agents are both highly individualized and clearly culturally defined, and where comparisons between alternatives are immediate because of inexpensive, complete information that can be confronted with univocal decision criteria. As noted by the anthropologist Jerome Davis (1973) in his critique of the economist theory of exchange, the situation that best corresponds to RAT is that of the consumer shopping in a supermarket. The question is whether it is acceptable to generalize the store paradigm into a “cafeteria conception of society” (Worsley, 1984, p. 246) or into a gigantic game of Monopoly.
58It is not enough, however, to inject a bit of culture or symbolism in order to escape the illusions of the RAT. We know that an analysis which proceeds, according to the Parsonsian model, by making culture the table of values and norms which fix the action’s objectives and which can be invoked to account, most often circularly, for almost any type of observed behavior, is just as unenlightening. To avoid this normativist trap, Ann Swidler (1986, p. 273) suggests infusing the analysis of culture with a strategic dimension by reconceptualizing it as “an array of symbols, stories, rituals, and worldviews that people can use in various configurations to solve different kinds of problems.” The causal analysis of behaviors then consists in showing how culture provides actors with the “prefabricated elements” from which they elaborate their strategies. Notwithstanding its intentions, such an approach does not get us out of the dead ends of the instrumentalist individualism of RAT, since it tends to reduce culture to a simple object, a means of action, rather than making it a constitutive or structuring element of practices. Although she recommends Bourdieu’s work, Swidler does not seem to perceive that the notion of cultural strategy that Bourdieu implements supposes neither conscious intentionality and calculating reason (Bourdieu, 1988), nor the deployment of individual strategies.
59There remains the thorny debate concerning the cross-cultural validity of the notion of rationality, very conveniently evaded by the Rats of all sides, but which also constitutes a major stumbling block for a historical sociology of culturalist inspiration. Pushed to their limit, the universalism of the RAT and cultural and historical particularism converge to make any social science impracticable, as revealed by the controversy provoked by the neo-Wittgensteinian thesis of Peter Winch in The Idea of a Social Science. [55] On the one hand, there is no doubt that the naive universalism of RAT is based on an ethnocentric projection of the analyst’s cultural presuppositions that denies them access to an adequate understanding of foreign cultures. On the other hand, the particularist argument pushed to its logical limits leads to a relativism that makes the notion of social knowledge highly problematic: if all knowledge is entirely dependent on its immediate context (“indexical” as ethnomethodologists say) and inseparable from the original “language game” in which it is formulated, then the very possibility of any cross-cultural understanding disappears. Some people, surfing on the post-modernist wave that has recently brought the nihilist critique of science back into fashion, have been quick to embrace this hyper-relativism and to deduce from its allegedly inescapable character the need to abandon the very project of a science of society. But as Charles Taylor (1985, chap. 4) has clearly seen, far from proceeding by static correspondence between concepts and linguistic references, inter-cultural understanding takes place through a process of mutual learning that transforms the two original conceptual registers.
60This opens the way for a reflexive social science capable of taking seriously the specificity of cultures and actors – including that of the analyst – without getting lost in it. In a similar way, recent advances in feminist theory have swept away the presupposition of sexual undifferentiation embedded in the ethnocentric universalism of RAT by exploding the idea of an actor without gender. [56] There are so many problems that it makes us wonder if there exists a methodological individualism that does not take as its starting point those “men in a state of fantastic isolation and rigidity” that Marx mocks (1967, p. 47-48); in short, that is, in the recent words of Michael Burawoy, something other than a “mythological individualism.” [57]
61But that is not all, because it would not be enough to historicize and sex up the notion of the individual and to release univocal and universal criteria of rationality to make up for the theoretical deficiencies of RAT. It is the model of science that it proposes that must be questioned in its turn. If we accept the utilitarian and individualistic premises of Coleman’s conception of action, we may ask ourselves whether economics offers the means to bridge the gap between theory and empiricism that he rightly deplores, given his disregard for empirical research. [58] The idea that economic science would progress, step by step, by dint of empirical tests of hypotheses logically deduced from the RAT, which underlies its representation as an ‘advanced’ science likely to serve as a model for sociology, a backward and immature science, is nothing more than a positivist illusion (Hollis and Nell, 1975). Moreover, it is paradoxical, to say the least, to invite sociologists to adopt neo-classical economic models at the very moment when their simplicity and unrealism make them the target of a radical challenge from within their mother discipline. [59] As Collins (1986a, p. 1352) notes:
“The rational choice model is an imperialist intrusion into sociology by economics which comes from the most classical and ‘backwards’ area of contemporary economics.”
63Universalizing the particular case of liberal economies with a high degree of objective rationalization, RAT, both in its sociological version and in its Marxist variant, projects the image of the capitalist market economy formed by neo-classical theory onto the whole of society. [60] In so doing, it refrains from discerning the multiple rationalities – and often irrationalities from the point of view of economics stricto sensu – that govern the various social fields. For (Bourdieu, 1987, p. 125; 1988):
“Far from being a sort of natural anthropological given, interest, in its historical specification, is an arbitrary institution. There is not one interest, but many interests, varying according to time and place, almost to infinity… The interest thus defined is the product of a determined category of social conditions: a historical construction, it can only be known by historical knowledge, ex post, empirically, and not deduced a priori from a transhistorical nature.”
65Thus, the notion of intentional strategy oriented only by the research of the interest of the “economic economy,” with all that it carries of deliberate decision, conscious calculation, rational reasoning, planned and reflected choice, and of “reasoning reason” (as opposed to practical reason), leads to projecting into reality the model which is supposed to give a reason for it and to attribute to the agents themselves the posture and the “rational” look of the analyst, transforming practice into an “imaginary activity of imaginary subjects” as Marx says in The German Ideology. RAT would not be so harmful to the development of a sociology of action if, under the guise of heuristics or theory, it did not carry in the background an atomistic ontology of the social which is at the same time a real scholarly denial of the social, of action and collective claims, of social movements and of the threatening political possibilities of which they are bearers. [61] By playing simultaneously on the registers of the model and of a derealized reality, by sliding insensitively from the analytical to the anthropological, the RAT lends to the agents the intellectualist relationship to practice which, as Pierre Bourdieu (1980, book I) underlines, owes its contemplative point of view on practice to the fact that it has to withdraw from it in order to take it as an object, and comes to confuse those decisive abstractions that are the rational reconstructions with reality itself.
66With so many presuppositions and blind spots the theory of rational action is not a solid or rigorous basis for a general theory of society, nor of the economy. This was clearly seen by Weber – whom certain Rats, notably in France, do not hesitate to call regularly and almost ritually to the aid of their cause [62] – when he insisted on the unbridgeable chasm that separates the practical logic of action from that of the model that the scientist builds for the purposes of analysis:
“For the purposes of a typological scientific analysis it is convenient to treat all irrational, affectually determined elements of behavior as factors of deviation from a conceptually pure type of rational action. […] Only in these respects and for these reasons of methodological convenience is the method of sociology ‘rationalistic’. It is naturally not legitimate to interpret this procedure as involving a rationalistic bias in sociology, but only as a methodological device. It certainly does not involve a belief in the actual predominance of rational elements in human life, for on the question of how far this predominance does or does not exist, nothing whatever has been said.” [63]
68And Weber (ibid., p. 7) warns us, with an astonishing sense of anticipation: “That there is, however, a danger of rationalistic interpretations where they are out of place cannot be denied.” It is to this theoretical sleight of hand, which consists in giving a theoretical model (which is, by the way, very simplistic) for a practical scheme, in formulating a generalized practice of the economy where there should be a generalized economy of practices, as much as to its obvious affinity with the dominant vision of the social order as a simple aggregation of freely consented individual choices and to its ability to exorcise the specter of collective action, that the theory of rational action owes its social success within the American academy.
Bibliography
- Abercrombie, Nicholas, Hill, Stephen & Turner, Bryan, 1980, The Dominant ldeology Thesis, London, George Allen and Unwin.
- Abercrombie, Nicholas, Hill, Stephen & Turner, Bryan, 1986, Sovereign Individuals of Capitalism, London, George Allen and Unwin.
- Abrams, Philip, 1982, Historical Sociology, Ithaca, Cornell University Press.
- Adler, Patricia, Adler, Peter & Fontana, Andrea, 1987, “Everyday Life Sociology”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 13, p. 217-235.
- Alexander, Jeffrey C., 1982-1983, Theoretical Logic in Sociology, Berkeley, University of California Press, 4 vols.
- Alexander, Jeffrey C., 1987, Twenty Lectures: Sociological Theory Since World War II, New York, Columbia University Press.
- Alexander, Jeffrey C., 1988a, Action and its Environments: Toward a New Synthesis, New York, Columbia University Press.
- Alexander, Jeffrey C., 1988b, “Parsons’ ‘Structure’ in American Sociology”, Sociological Theory, 6(1), p. 96-102.
- Alexander, Jeffrey C., 1988c, “The New Theoretical Movement”, in N. J. Smelser (ed.), Handbook of Modem Sociology, Beverly Hills, Sage.
- Alexander, Jeffrey C. (ed.), 1985, Neo-Functionalism, Beverly Hills, Sage.
- Alexander, Jeffrey C., Giesen, Bernhard, Munch, Richard & Smelser, Neil J. (eds.), 1987, The Micro-Macro Link, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Aminzade, Ron, 1981, Class, Politics and Early Industrial Capitalism, Albany, State University of New York Press.
- Atkinson, Paul, 1988, “Ethnomethodology: A Critical Review”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 14, p. 441-465.
- Barry, Brian, 1978, Sociologists, Economists and Democracy, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Becker, Gary S., 1976, The Economics Approach to Human Behavior, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Becker, Gary S., 1981, A Treatise on the Family, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Becker, Howard S., 1982, Art Worlds, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Bellah, Robert N. et al., 1985, Habits of the Heart, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Benhabib, Seyla, & Cornell, Drucilla, 1987, Feminism as Critique, Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press.
- Ben-Porath, Yoram, 1980, “The F-Connection: Families, Friends, and Firms and the Organization of Exchange”, Population Development Review, vol. 6, p. 1-29.
- Berg, lvar (ed.), 1981, Sociological Perspectives on Labor Markets, New York, Academic Press.
- Berger, Bennett, 1981, The Survival of a Counter Culture, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Blau, Judith R., 1988, The Shape of Culture, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Blau, Peter M., 1977a, Inequalitv and Heterogeneity, New York, The Free Press.
- Blau, Peter M., 1977b, “A Macrosociological Theory of Social Structure”, American Journal of Sociology, 83(1), p. 26-54.
- Blau, Peter M., 1986, “Preface” in: Exchange and Power in Social Life, New Brunswick, Transaction Books.
- Block, Fred, 1977, The Origins of International Economy Disorder, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Bonnell, Victoria, 1983, The Russian Worker, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Boudon, Raymond, 1979, La logique du social, Paris, Hachette.
- Boudon, Raymond, 1984, La place du désordre, Paris, Presses Universitaires de France.
- Boudon, Raymond, 1986, L’idéologie. L’origine des idées reçues, Paris, Fayard.
- Boulding, Kenneth, 1969, “Economies as a Moral Science”, American Economics Review, 59(1), p. 1-12.
- Bourdieu, Pierre, 1980, Le sens pratique, Paris, Éditions de Minuit.
- Bourdieu, Pierre, 1987, « L’intérêt du sociologue », in Choses dites, Paris, Éditions de Minuit, p. 124-131.
- Bourdieu, Pierre, 1988, On Interest and the Relative Autonomy of Symbolic Power, Working Papers and Proceedings of the Center for Psychosocial Studies, n° 20, Chicago, Center for Psychosocial Studies.
- Bourdieu, Pierre, Chartier, Roger & Darnton, Robert, 1985, « Dialogues à propos de l’histoire culturelle », Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales, vol. 59, p. 86-93.
- Brewer, John, 1987, “Exploitation in the New Marxism of Collective Action”, The Sociological Review, 35(1), p. 84-93.
- Brubaker, Rogers, 1984, The Limits of Rationality, London, George Allen and Unwin.
- Bryant, Christopher G. A., 1985, Positivism in Social Theory and Research, New York, Saint Martin’s Press.
- Burawoy, Michael, 1985, The Politics of Production, London, Verso.
- Burawoy, Michael, 1987, “The Limits of Wright’s Analytical Marxism and an Alternative”, Berkeley Journal of Sociology, vol. 32, p. 51-72.
- Burawoy, Michael, 1986-1989, “Making Nonsense of Marx”, Contemporary Sociology, 15(5), p. 704-707, (in press) Marxism Without Micro-Foundations, Przeworski’s Critique of Social Democracy, Socialist Review.
- Burke Edinund, III (ed.), 1988, Global Crises and Social Movements, Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press.
- Burt, Ronald S., 1982, Toward a Structural Theory of Action: Network Models of Social Structure, Perception and Action, New York, Academic Press.
- Calhoun, Craig J., 1982, The Question of Class Struggle, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Calhoun, Craig J., 1987, “History and Sociology in Britain: A Review Article”, Comparative Studies in Society and History, 29(3), p. 615-625.
- Camic, Charles, 1979, “The Utilitarians Revisited”, American Journal of Sociology, 85(3), p. 516-550.
- Camic, Charles, 1986, “The Return of the Functionalists”, Contemporarv Sociology, 15(5), p. 692-695.
- Carling, Alan, 1986, “Rational Choice Marxism”, New Left Review, vol. 160, p. 24-62.
- Carrithers, Michael, Collins, Steven & Lukes, Steven (eds.), 1985, The Category of the Person: Anthropology, Philosophy, History, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Chirot, Daniel, 1976, Social Change in the Modem World, New York, Harcourt-Brace-Jovanovitch.
- Chirot, Daniel & Hall, Thomas, 1982, “World-System Theory”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 8, p. 81-106.
- Clark, Samuel D., 1976, Canadian Society in Historical Perspective, Toronto, McGraw-Hill Ryerson.
- Cohen, Gerald A., 1978, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence, Princeton, Princeton University Princeton Press.
- Cohen, Jean L., 1985, “Strategy or Identity: New Theoretical Paradigms and Contemporary Social Movements”, Social Research, 52(4), p. 663-716.
- Colin, Bernard S., 1980, “History and Anthropology: The State of Play”, Comparative Studies in Society and History, 22(2), p. 198-221.
- Colin, Bernard S., 1988, An Anthropologist Among the Historians and Other Essays, New York, Oxford University Press.
- Coleman, James S., 1961, The Adolescent Society, New York, The Free Press.
- Coleman, James S., 1973, The Mathematics of Collective Action, London, Heinemann.
- Coleman, James S., 1974a, “Inequality, Sociology, and Moral Philosophy”, American Journal of Sociology, 80(3), p. 739-764.
- Coleman, James S., 1974b, Power and the Structure of Society, New York, W. W. Norton and Co.
- Coleman, James S., 1978, “Sociological Analysis and Social Policy”, in Tom B. Bottomore and Robert A. Nisbet (eds.), A History of Sociological Analysis, New York, Basic Books, p. 677-703.
- Coleman, James S., 1979, “Rational Choice Theory and Macrosociological Analysis”, in Ross Harrison (ed.), Rational Action: Philosophy and Social Science, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Coleman, James S., 1982, The Asymmetric Society, Syracuse, Syracuse University Press.
- Coleman, James S., 1984, “Introducing Social Structure into Economic Analysis”, The American Economic Review, 74(2), p. 84-88.
- Coleman, James S., 1986a, Social Theory, Social Research, and a Theory of Action, American Journal of Sociology, 91(6), p. 1309-1335.
- Coleman, James S., 1986b, “Micro Foundations and Macrosocial Theory”, in Siegwart Lindenberg, James S. Coleman and Stephan Nowak (eds.), Approaches to Social Theory, New York, Russell Sage Foundation, p. 344-363.
- Coleman, James S., 1986c, Individual Interests and Collective Action, Cambridge. Cambridge University Press.
- Coleman, James S., 1986d, “Psychological Structure and Social Structure in Economic Models”, Journal of Business, 59(4), supplement, p. S365-S369.
- Coleman, James S., 1986e, “Social Structure and the Emergence of Norms Among Rational Actors”, in A. Dickmann and P. Mitter (eds.), Paradoxical Effects of Social Behavior: Essays in Honor of Anatol Rappoport, Vienna, Physica Verlag.
- Coleman, James S., 1987a, “Actors and Action in Social History and Social Theory: Reply to Sewell”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(1), July, p. 172-175.
- Coleman, James S., 1987b, “Microfoundations and Macrosocial Behavior”, in Alexander et al., (eds.), The Micro-Macro Link, Berkeley, University of California Press, p. 153-173.
- Coleman, James S., 1987c, “Norms as Social Capital”, in Gérard Radnitzky and Peter Bernholz (eds.), Economic Imperialism, New York, Paragon, p. 133-155.
- Coleman, James S., 1988a, “Social Capital in the Creation of Human Capital”, in Christopher Winship and Sherwood Rosen (eds.), Organizations and Institutions, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press, p. 95-120.
- Coleman, James S., 1988b, “Free Riders and Zealots: The Role of Social Networks”, Sociological Theory, 6(1), p. 52-57.
- Coleman, James S., (forthcoming), Foundations of Social Theory, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Coleman, James S. et al., 1966, Equality of Educational Opportunity, Washington, D. C., Government Printing Office.
- Coleman, James S. & Hoffer, Thomas B., 1986, Public and Private High Schools: The Impact of Communities, New York, Basic Books.
- Collins, Randall, 1981, “On the Microfoundations of Macrosociology”, American Journal of Sociology, 86(5), p. 984-1014.
- Collins, Randall, 1983, “Micro-Methods as a Basis for Macro-Sociology”, Urban Life, vol. 12, p. 184-202.
- Collins, Randall, 1985, Three Sociological Traditions, New York, Oxford University Press.
- Collins, Randall, 1986a, “Is 1980s Sociology in the Doldrums?”, American Journal of Sociology, 91(6), p. 1336-1355.
- Collins, Randall, 1986b, Weberian Sociological Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Collins, Randall, 1987, “Looking Forward or Looking Back? Reply to Denzin”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(1), p. 180-184.
- Collins, Randall, 1988, Theoretical Sociology, New York, Harcourt-Brace-Jovanovitch.
- Comaroff, Jean, 1985, Body of Power. Stories of Resistance: The Culture and History of a South African People, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Comaroff, Jean & Comaroff, John L., 1986, “Christianity and Colonialism in South Africa”, The American Ethnologist, 13(1), p. 1-22.
- Comaroff, Jean, 1982, “Dialectical Systems, History, and Anthropology: Units of Analysis and Questions of Theory”, Journal of Southern African Studies, 8(2), p. 143-172.
- Corrigan, Paul & Sayer, David, 1985, The Great Arch: English State Formation as a Cultural Revolution, London, Basil Blackwell.
- Crapanzano, Vincent, 1986, “Hermes’ Dilemma: The Masking of Subversion in Ethnographic Description”, in James Clifford and George E. Marcus (eds.), Writing Culture: Ethnography as Poetics and Politics, Berkeley, University of California Press, p. 51-76.
- Darnton, Robert, 1984, The Great Cat Slaughter, Paris, Robert Laffont.
- Davis, Jerome, 1973, “Forms and Norms: The Economy of Social Relations”, Man, 8(2), new series, p. 159-176.
- Denzin, Norman K., 1984, On Understanding Emotions, San Francisco, Jossey-Bass.
- Denzin, Norman K., 1987a, “The Death of Sociology in the 1980s: Comment on Collins”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(1), p. 175-180.
- Denzin, Norman K., 1987b, The Recovering Alcoholic, Newberry Park, Sage.
- Desan, Philippe, Parkhurst Ferguson, Priscilla & Griswold, Wendy (eds.), 1989, Literature and Social Practice, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- DiMaggio, Paul (ed.), 1986, Nonprofit Enterprise in the Arts, New York, Oxford University Press.
- Douglas, Mary, 1986, How Institutions Think, Syracuse, Syracuse University Press.
- Downs, Anthony, 1957, An Economy Theory of Democracy, New York, Harper and Row.
- Elias, Norbert, 1973, The Civilization of Manners, Paris, Calmann-Levy.
- Elias, Norbert, 1985, “Remarks on gossip”, Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales, vol. 60, p. 23-30.
- Elster, Jon, 1979, “Anomalies and Rationality: Some Unresolved Problems in the Theory of Rational Behavior”, in L. Levy-Garboua (ed.), Sociological Economies, London, Sage, p. 68-85.
- Elster, Jon, 1981, “An English Marxism: About a new interpretation of historical materialism historical materialism”, Annals: economies, societies, civilizations, n° 5, p. 745-757.
- Elster, Jon, 1985, Making Sense of Marx, Cambridge and Paris, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.
- Elster, Jon (ed.), 1986, Rational Choice, London, Basil Blackwell.
- Evans, Peter B., 1978, Dependent Development: The Alliance of Multinational. State and Local Capital in Brazil, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
- Faina, Eugene F., 1980, “Agency Problems and the Theory of the Firm”, Journal of Political Economy, 88(2), p. 288-307.
- Fine, Gary Allan, 1987, With the Boys: Little League Baseball and Preadolescent Culture, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Fireman, Bruce & Gamson, William A., 1979, “Utilitarian Logic in the Resource Mobilization Perspective”, in Mayer Zald and J.D. McCarthy (cds.), The Dynamics of Social Movements, Cambridge, Winthrop.
- Foucault, Michel, 1975, Surveiller et punir. Naissance de la prison, Paris, Gallimard.
- Foucault, Michel, 1976, Histoire de la sexualité, vol. 1 : La volonté de savoir, Paris, Gallimard.
- Francis, Arthur, Turk, Jeremy & Willman, Paul (eds.), 1983, Power, Efficiencv and Institutions: A Critical Appraisal of the “Markets and Hierarchies” Paradigm, London, Heinemann.
- Gambetta, Diego, 1987, Did they jump or were they pushed? Individual Decision Mechanisms in Education, Cambridge and Paris, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.
- Garfinkel, Harold, 1967, Studies in Ethnomethodology, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice-Hall.
- Geertz, Clifford, 1974, The Interpretation of Cultures, New York, Basic Books.
- Geison, Gerald L. (ed.), 1984, Professions and the French State, 1700-1900, Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press.
- Gibson, Mary, 1977, Rationality, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6(3), p. 193-225.
- Giddens, Anthony, 1977, “Four Myths in the History of Social Thought”, in Studies in Social and Political Theory, New York, Basic Books, p. 208-234.
- Giddens, Anthony, 1979, Central Problems in Social Theory: Action. Structure, and Contradiction in Social Analysis, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Giddens, Anthony, 1984, The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of Structuration, Cambridge, Polity Press.
- Giddens, Anthony, 1987, Social Theory and Modem Sociology, Cambridge, Polity Press.
- Giddens, Anthony & Turner, Jonathan H. (eds.), 1987, Social Theory Today, Cambridge, Polity Press and Stanford, Stanford University Press.
- Gilligan, Carol, 1982, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Goffman, Erving, 1974, Frame Analysis, New York, Basic Book.
- Granovetter, Mark S., 1973, “The Strength of Weak Ties”, American Journal of Sociology, 78(6), p. 1360-1380.
- Granovetter, Mark S., 1974, Getting a Job: A Study of Contacts and Careers, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Granovetter, Mark S., 1985, “Economy Action and Social Structure: The Problem of Embededness”, American Journal of Sociology, 91(3), p. 481-510.
- Griswold, Wendy, 1986, Renaissance Revivals: City Comedy and Revenge Tragedy in the London Theatre. 1576-1980, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Gusfield, Joseph R., 1981, The Culture of Public Problems, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Gutman, Herbert G., 1987, Power and Culture: Essays on the American Working Class, New York, Pantheon. Edited by Ira Berlin.
- Hall, John, 1985, Powers and Liberties, London, Basil Blackwell.
- Hall, Stuart & Jefferson, Tony (eds.), 1976, Resistance Through Rituals, London, Hutchinson.
- Hardin, Russell, 1982, Collective Action, Baltimore, The Johns Hopkins University Press.
- Hardin, Russell, 1983, “Difficulties with the Notion of Economic Rationality”, Social Science News, 23(3), p. 453-468.
- Haydu, Jeffrey, 1988, Between Craft and Class: Skilled Workers and Factory Politics in the United States and Great Britain. 1890-1922, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Heath, Anthony, 1976, Rational Choice and Social Exchange, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Hebdige, Dick, 1979, Subculture: The Meaning of Style, London, Methuen.
- Hechter, Michael, 1975, Internal Colonialism: The Celtic Fringe in British National Development. 1536-1966, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Hechter, Michael, 1987, Principles of Group Solidarity, Berkeley. University of California Press.
- Hechter, Michael (ed.), 1983, The Microfoundations of Macrosociology, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
- Heritage, John C., 1985, “Recent Developments in Conversational Analysis”, Sociolinguistics, vol. 15, p. 1-18.
- Hinckle, Roscoe C. & Hinckle, Gisela J., 1980, Founding Theory of American Sociology, 1881-1915, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Hindess, Barry, 1984, “Rational Choice Theory and the Analysis of Political Action”, Economy and Society, 13(3), p. 255-277.
- Hindess, Barry, 1986, note Jon Elster, “Making Sense of Marx”, The Sociological Review, 34(2), p. 440-442.
- Hirsch, Paul, Michaels, Stuart & Friedman, Ray, 1987, “’Dirty Hands’ versus ‘Clean Models’: Is Sociology in Danger of Being Seduced By Economies?”, Theory and Society, 16(3), p. 317-336.
- Hirshleifer, Jack, 1985, “The Expanding Domain of Economies”, The American Economy Review, 75(1), March, p. 53-68.
- Hirschman, Albert O., 1982, Shifting Involvements: Private Interests and Public Action, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
- Hirschman, Albert O., 1986, Vers une économie politique élargie, Paris, Éditions de Minuit.
- Hochschild, Arlie Russell, 1979, “Emotion Work, Feeling Rules, and Social Structure”, American Journal of Sociology, 85(3), p. 551-575.
- Hochschild, Arlie Russell, 1983, The Managed Heart, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Hollis, Martin, 1977, Models of Man, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Hollis, Martin, 1987, The Cunning of Reason, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Hollis, Martin & Lukes, Steven (eds.), 1982, Rationality and Relativism, Cambridge, MIT Press.
- Hollis, Martin & Nell, Edward, 1975, Rational Economic Man, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Homans, George Caspar, 1986, “Fifty Years of Sociology”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 12, p. 12-30.
- Homans, George Caspar, 1987, “Collective Choice”, Contemporary Sociology, 16(6), p. 769-770.
- Homans, George Caspar, 1989, “Rational Choice Theory and Behaviorism”, in Craig J. Calhoun, Marshall Meyer and W. Richard Scott (eds.), Structures of Power and Constraint: Papers in Honor of Peter M. Blau, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press (in press).
- Hunt, Lynn, 1984, Politics, Culture and Class in the French Revolution, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Jenkins, Craig J., 1983, “Resource Mobilization Theory and the Study of Social Movements”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 9, p. 527-533.
- Kemper, Theodore K., 1978, A Social Interactional Theory or Emotions, New York, Wiley.
- Katznelson, Ira, 1981, City Trenches: Urban Politics and the Pattern of Class in the United States, New York, Pantheon Books.
- Katnelson, Ira J. & Zolberg, Aristide R. (eds.), 1986, Working-Class Formation: Nineteenth-Century Patterns in Western Europe and the United States, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
- Kieve, Ronald A., 1986, From Necessary Illusion to Rational Choice? A Critique of Neo-Marxist Rational-Choice Theory, Theory and Society, 15(4), p. 557-582.
- Knorr-Cetina, Karen, 1981, “The Micro-Sociological Challenge of Macro-Sociology in: Karen Knorr-Cetina and Aaron V. Cicourel” (eds.), Advances in Social Theory and Methodology, Boston and London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, p. 1-47.
- Knorr-Cetina, Karen & Cicourel, Aaron V. (eds.), 1981, Advances in Social Theory and Methodology: Toward an Integration of Micro- and Macro-Sociologies, Boston and London, Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Laitin, David, 1986, Hegemony and Culture: The Politics of Religious Change Among the Yoruba, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Lash, Scott & Urry, John, 1984, “The New Marxism of Collective Action”, Sociology, 18(1), p. 33-50.
- Latsis, Spiro, 1972, “Situational Determinism in Economies”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, vol. 23, p. 207-225.
- Laumann, Edward O. & Knoke, David, 1987, The Organizational State, Madison, University of Wisconsin Press.
- Leifer, Eric M., 1985, “Markets as Mechanisms: Using a Role Structure”, Social Forces, 64(2), p. 442-472.
- Levine, Andrew, Sober, Elliot & Wright, Erik Olin, 1987, “Marxism and Methodological Individualism”, New Left Review, vol. 162, p. 67-84.
- Levine, David (ed.), 1984, Proletarianization and Family History, Orlando, Academic Press.
- Levine, Donald N., 1985, The Flight from Ambiguity: Essays in Social and Cultural Theory, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Lewis, J. David & Smith, Richard L., 1980, American Sociology and Pragmatism, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Lieberson, Stanley, 1980, A Piece of the Pie, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Lieberson, Stanley, 1984, Making it Count: The Improvement of Social Theory and Social Research, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Lieberstein, Harvey, 1976, Beyond Economics Man: A New Foundation for Microeconomics, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Lieberstein, Harvey, 1979, “A Branch of Economies is Missing: The Micro-Macro Link”, Journal of Economic Literature, 17(2), p. 477-502.
- Lindenberg, Siegwart, Coleman, James S. & Nowak, Stephan (eds.), 1986, Approaches to Social Theory, New York, Russell Sage Foundation.
- Lofland, Lynn H., 1985, “The Social Shaping of Emotions: The Case of Grief”, Symbolic Interaction, 8(2), p. 171-190.
- Luke, Timothy, 1985, “Reason and Rationality in Rational Choice Theory”, Social Research, 52(1), p. 65-98.
- Lutz, Catherine A., 1988, Unnatural Emotions: Everyday Sentiments on a Micronesian Atoll and their Challenge to Western Theory, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- McNall, Scott G., 1988, The Road to Rebellion: Class Formation and Kansas Populism. 1865-1900, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Macpherson, C. B., 1962, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
- Mann, Michael, 1986, The Sources of Social Power. Vol. 1, A History of Power from the Beginning to A. D. 1760, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Marx, Karl & Engels, Friedrich, 1967, The German Ideology, New York, International Publishers.
- Miller, Harlan B. & Williams, William H. (eds.), 1982, The Limits of Utilitarianism. Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press.
- Mills, C. Wright, 1959, The Sociological Imagination, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
- Moe, Terry M., 1984, “The New Economies of Organization”, American Journal of Political Science, 28(4), p. 739-777.
- Moore, Barrington, Jr., 1978, Injustice: The Social Bases of Obedience and Revolt, White Plains, New York, M.E. Sharp.
- Morawska, Eva, 1985, For Bread and Butter: Lifeworld’s of East-Central Europeans in Jonestown. Pennsylvania. 1890-1940, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Munch, Richard, 1987, “Parsonian Theory Today: In Search of a New Synthesis”, in Anthony Giddens and Jonathan H. Turner (eds.), Social Theory Today, Cambridge, Polity Press, p. 116-145.
- Obershall, Anthony, 1973, Social Movements and Social Conflict, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice-Hall.
- Oberschall, Anthony & Leifer, Eric M., 1986, “Efficiency and Social Institutions: Uses and Misuses of Economic Reasoning in Sociology”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 12, p. 233-253.
- Oliver, Pamela, 1980, “Rewards and Punishments as Selective Incentives for Collective Action: Theoretical Investigations”, American Journal of Sociology, 85(6), p. 1356-1375.
- Olson, Mancur, 1965, The Logic of Collective Action, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Padioleau, Jean, 1986, L’ordre social. Principes d’analyse sociologique, Paris, L’Harmattan.
- Paige, Jeffrey, 1975, Agrarian Revolution, New York, The Free Press.
- Parkin, Frank, 1979, Marxism and Class Theory: A Bourgeois Critique, New York, Columbia University Press.
- Parsons, Talcott, 1937, The Structure of Social Action, Glencoe, The Free Press.
- Patterson, Orlando, 1984, Slavery as Social Death, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Peterson, Richard A., 1979, “Revitalizing the Culture Concept”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 5, p. 137-166.
- Perrow, Charles, 1986, “Economics Theories of Organization”, in Complex Organizations: A Critical Essay, New York, Random House, 3rd ed. p. 219-257.
- Plott, Charles R., 1976, “Axiomatic Social Choice Theory: An Overview and Interpretation”, American Journal of Political Science, 20(3), p. 511-596.
- Poggi, Gianfranco, 1978, The Development of the Modem State: A Sociological Introduction, Stanford, Stanford University Press.
- Popkin, Samuel, 1979, The Rational Peasant, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Portes, Alejandro, 1976, “The Sociology of National Development: Theories and Issues”, American Journal of Sociologv, 82(1), p. 55-85.
- Powell, Walter W., 1985, Getting Into Print: The Decision-Making Process in Scholarly Publishing, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Pratt, John W. & Zeckhauser, Richard J. (eds.), 1985, Principals and Agents: The Structure of Business, Boston, Harvard Business School Press.
- Przeworski, Adam, 1985a, Marxism and Rational Choice, Politics and Society, 14(4), p. 379-409.
- Przeworski, Adam, 1985b, Capitalism and Social Democracy, Cambridge and Paris, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.
- Psathas, George (ed.), 1979, Everyday Language: Studies in Ethnomethodology, New York, Irvington Press.
- Quadagno, Jill, 1988, The Transformation of Old Age Security: Class and Politics in the American, Welfare State, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Rabinow, Paul & Sullivan, William M. (eds.), 1979 [1988], Interpretive Social Science: A Reader, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Radnitzky, Gerard & Bernholz, Peter (eds.), 1987, Economics Imperialism, New York, Paragon.
- Ragin, Charles, 1987, The Comparative Method: Moving Beyond Qualitative and Quantitative Strategies, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Riker, William H. & Ordeshook, Peter C., 1973, An Introduction to Positive Political Theory, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice Hall.
- Rochberg-Halton, Eugene, 1986, Meaning and Modernity: Social Theory in the Pragmatic Attitude, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Roemer, John E., 1981, Analytical Foundations of Marxian Economic Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Roemer, John E., 1982a, A General Theory of Exploitation and Class, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Roemer, John E., 1982b, “Methodological Individualism and Deductive Marxism”, Theory and Society, 11(4), p. 253-287.
- Roemer, John E., 1988, Free To Lose. An Introduction to Marxist Economics Philosophy, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Roemer, John E. (ed.), 1986, Analytical Marxism, Cambridge and Paris, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.
- Rosaldo, Michèle, 1980, Knowledge and Passion. Ilongot Notions of Self and Social Life, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Rosaldo, Renato, 1980, Ilongot Headhunting. 1883-1974: A Study in Society and History, Stanford, Stanford University Press.
- Roseberry, William, 1982, “Balinese Cockfight and the Seduction of Anthropology”, Social Research, 49(4), p. 1013-1028.
- Roth, Paul A., 1987, Meaning and Method in the Social Sciences: A Case for Methodological Pluralism Ithaca and London, Cornell University Press.
- Roy, William G., 1984, “Class Conflict and Social Change in Historical Perspective”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 10, p. 483-506.
- Rueschemeyer, Dietrisch, 1973, Lawyers and their Society, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Rueschemeyer, Dietrisch, 1986, Power and the Division of Labor, Stanford, Stanford University Press.
- Rueschemeyer, Dietrisch, Evans, Peter B. & Skocpol, Theda R. (eds.), 1985, Bringing the State Back In, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Rule, James B., 1988, Theories of Civil Violence, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Sahel, Charles F., 1984, Work and Politics: The Division of Labor in Industry, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Sahlins, Marshall, 1981, Historical Metaphors and Mythical Realities, Ann Arbor, University of Michigan Press.
- Sahlins, Marshall, 1985, Islands of History, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Sarfatti-Larson, Margaret, 1977, The Rise of Professionalism: A Sociological Analysis, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Schutz, Alfred, 1943, “The Problem of Rationality in the Social World”, Economica, vol. 10 (new series), p. 130-149.
- Schutz, Alfred, 1970, On Phenomenology and Social Relations, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press, edited by Helmut R. Wagner.
- Schwartz, Mildred, 1987, “Historical Sociology in the History of American Sociology”, Social Science History, 11(1), p. 1-16.
- Schneider, Mark A., 1987, “Culture-as-Text in the Work of Clifford Geertz”, Theory and Society, 16(6), p. 809-839.
- Sciulli, David & Gerstein, Dean, 1985, “Social Theory and Talcott Parsons in the 1980s”, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 11, p. 369-387.
- Scott, Joan Wallach, 1988, Gender and the Politics of History, New York, Columbia University Press.
- Sen, Amartya K., 1977, “Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economies”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 6(4), p. 317-344.
- Sen, Amartya K. & Williams, Bernard (eds.), 1982, Utilitarianism and Beyond, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Sennett, Richard, 1977, The Fall of Public Man, New York, Knopf.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1974a, “Social Change and the Rise of Working-Class Politics in Nineteenth-Century Marseilles”, Past and Present, vol. 65, p. 75-109.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1974b, “Etats, Corps and Ordre: Some Notes on the Social Vocabulary of the French Old Regime”, in H.-U. Wehler (ed.), Sozialgeschichte Heute: Festschrift fur Hans Rosenberg zum 70 Geburstag, Gottingen, Vandenhoek und Ruprecht.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1979, “Corporations Républicaines: The Revolutionary Idiom of Parisian Workers in 1848”, Comparative Studies in Society and History, 21(2), p. 195-203.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1980, Work and Revolution in France: The Language of Labor from the Old Regime to 1848, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1981, « La confraternité des prolétaires : conscience de classe sous la Monarchie de Juillet », Annales: Economies, Societies, Civilisations, n° 4, p. 650-671.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1985a, The Men and Women of Marseilles. 1820-1870, Cambridge and Paris, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1985b, “Ideologies and Social Revolutions: Reflections on the French Case”, Journal of Modem History, 57(1), p. 57-85.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1986, “Artisans, Factory Workers, and the Formation of the French Working Class, 1789-1848”, in Ira J. Katznelson and Aristide R. Zolberg (eds.), Working-Class Formation, Princeton, Princeton University Press, p. 45-70.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1987, “Theory of Action, Dialectic and History: Comment on Coleman”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(1), p. 166-172.
- Sewell, William H. Jr., 1988, “Uneven Development, the Autonomy of Politics, and the Dockworkers of Nineteenth-Century Marseilles”, American Historical Review, vol. 93.
- Sewell, William H. Sr., 1988, “The Changing Institutional Structure of Sociology and My Career”, in Mathilda White Riley (ed.), Sociological Lives, Beverly Hills, Sage.
- Shankman, Paul, 1984, “The Thick and the Thin: On the Interpretive Theoretical Program of Clifford Geertz”, Current Anthropology, 25(3), p. 261-70.
- Shott, Susan, 1979, “Emotion and Social Life: A Symbolic Interactionist Analysis”, American Journal of Sociology, 84(6), p. 1317-1334.
- Sica, Alan, 1988, Weber, Irrationality and Social Order, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Skocpol, Theda R., 1979, States and Social Revolution, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Skocpol, Theda R., 1982, “Rentier State and Shi’a Islam in the Iranian Revolution”, Theory and Society, 11(2), p. 265-284.
- Skocpol, Theda R., 1985, “Cultural Idioms and Political Ideologies in the Revolutionary Reconstruction of State Power: A Rejoinder to Sewell”, Journal of Modem History, 57(1), p. 86-96.
- Skocpol, Theda R., 1987, “Social History and Historical Sociology: Contrasts and Complementarities”, Social Science History, 11(1), p. 17-30.
- Skocpol, Theda R. (ed.), 1984, Vision and Method in Historical Sociology, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Stark, David, 1986, “Rethinking Internal Labor Markets: New Insights from a Comparative Perspective”, American Sociological Review, 51(4), p. 492-504.
- Starr, Paul, 1982, The Social Transformation of American Medicine, New York, Basic Books.
- Stinchcombe, Arthur L., 1978, Theoretical Methods in Social History, New York, Academic Press.
- Stinchcombe, Arthur L., 1983, Economics Sociology, New York, Academic Press.
- Swedberg, Richard, Himmelstrand, Ulf & Brulin, Göran, 1987, “The Paradigm of Economic Sociology: Premises and Promises”, Theory and Society, 16(2), p. 169-214.
- Swidler, Ann, 1986, “Culture in Action: Symbols and Strategies”, American Sociological Review, 51(2), p. 273-286.
- Sztompka, Piotr, 1986, “The Renaissance of Historical Orientation in Sociology”, International Sociology, vol. 1, p. 321-337.
- Taylor, Charles, 1980, “Formal Theory in Social Science”, Inquiry, 23(2), p. 139-144.
- Taylor, Charles, 1985, Philosophical Papers II: Philosophy and the Human Mind, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- Taylor, Michael (ed.), 1988, Rationality and Revolution. Cambridge and Paris, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.
- Tilly, Charles, 1978, From Mobilization to Revolution, Reading (Massachusetts), Addison-Wesley.
- Tilly, Charles, 1981, As Sociology Meets History, New York, Academic Press.
- Tilly, Charles, 1984a, Big Structures, Large Processes, Huge Comparisons, New York, Russel Sage Foundation.
- Tilly, Charles, 1984b, “Review Essay: Sludge in the Growth Machine”, American Journal of Sociology, 89(5), p. 1214-1218.
- Tilly, Charles, 1985, The Contentious French, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Tilly, Charles, Tilly Louise & Tilly, Richard, 1975, The Rebellious Century, Cambridge, Harvard University Press.
- Traugott, Mark, 1985, Armies of the Poor, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
- Trimberger, Ellen K., 1978, Revolution From Above: Military Bureaucrats and Development in Japan, Turkey, Egypt and Peru, New Brunswick, Transaction Books.
- Turner, Jonathan H., 1988, The Structure of Social Interaction, Stanford, Stanford University Press.
- Turner, Jonathan H. & Maryanski, A.R., 1988, “Is ‘Neofunctionalism’ Really Functional”, Sociological Theory, 6(1), p. 1 10-121.
- Van Parijs, Philippe, 1981a, Evolutionary Explanation in the Social Sciences, Totowa, Rowman and Littlefield.
- Van Parijs, Philippe, 1981b, “Sociology as General Economies”, European Archives of Sociology, 22(2), p. 299-324.
- Van Parijs, Philippe, 1986-1987, “A Revolution in Class Theory”, Politics and Society, 15(4), p. 453-482.
- Wallace, Anthony F. C., 1978, Rockdale: The Growth of An American Village in the Early Industrial Revolution, New York, Knopf.
- Wallace, Anthony F. C., 1987, St. Clair: A Nineteenth-Century Coal Town’s Experience with a Disaster-Prone Industry, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
- Wallerstein, Immanuel, 1974, The Modem World System I, New York, Academic Press.
- Wallerstein, Immanuel, 1979, The Capitalist World-Economy, Cambridge and Paris, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences de l’Homme.
- Wallerstein, Immanuel, 1984, The Politics of the World-Economy, Cambridge and Paris, Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison de Sciences de l’Homme.
- Wallerstein, Immanuel, 1986, “Marxisms as Utopias: Evolving Ideologies”, American Journal of Sociology, 91(6), p. 1295-1308.
- Wallerstein, Immanuel, 1987, “World-Systems Analysis”, in Anthony Giddens and Jonathan H. Turner (cds.), Social Theory Today, Cambridge, Polity Press, p. 309-324.
- Walters, Ronald G., 1980, “Signs of the Times: Clifford Geertz and Historians”, Social Research, 47(3), p. 537-56.
- Wardell, Mark Li & Turner, Stephen P. (eds.), 1986, Sociological Theory in Transition, London, George Allen and Unwin.
- Weber, Max, 1978, Economy and Society, Berkeley, University of California Press, vol. 1.
- Weir, Margaret, Shola Orloff, Ann & Skocpol, Theda R. (eds.), 1988, The Politics of Social Policy in the United States, Princeton, Princeton University Press.
- Weldes, John & Duvall, Robert D., 1987, “Marxism Without Marx”, Contemporary Sociology, 16(6), p. 797-799.
- Wellman, Barry & Berkowitz, S. D. (eds.), 1988, Social Structures: A Network Approach, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- White, Harrison C., 1970, Chains of Opportunity, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
- White, Harrison C., 1981, “Where Do Markets Come From?”, American Journal of Sociology, 87(3), p. 517-547.
- White, James W., 1988, “Rational Rioters: Leaders, Followers, and Popular Protest in Early Modern Japan”, Politics and Society, 16(1), p. 35-70.
- Wilentz, Sean, 1984, Songs of Democracy: New York City and the Rise of the American Working Class. 1790-1850, New York, Oxford University Press.
- Wiley, Norbert, 1985, “The Current Interregnum in American Sociology”, Social Research, 52(1), p. 180-207.
- Williamson, Oliver, 1975, Markets and Hierarchies, New York, The Free Press.
- Williamson, Oliver, 1981, “The Economies of Organization: The Transaction Cost Approach”, American Journal of Sociology, 87(3), p. 548-577.
- Willis, Paul, 1977, Learning to Labor: How Working-Class Kids Get Working-Class Jobs, New York: Columbia University Press.
- Wilson, Bryan R. (ed.), 1970, Rationality, Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
- Wilson, William Julius, 1980, The Declining Significance of Race, Chicago and London, The University of Chicago Press, 2nd ed. [French translation to be published by Éditions de Minuit.]
- Winch, Peter, 1958, The Idea of a Social Science, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Winship, Christopher & Rosen, Sherwin (eds.), 1988, Organizations and Institutions: Sociological and Economic Approaches to the Analysis of Social Structures, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 1965, On Certainty, Paris, Gallimard.
- Wolf, Eric R., 1982, Europe and the People Without History, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Worsley, Peter, 1984, The Three Worlds: Culture and World Development, London, Weidenfeld and Nicholson.
- Wright, Erik Olin, 1985, Classes, London, Verso.
- Wrong, Dennis, 1961, “The Oversocialized Conception of Man”, American Sociological Review, 26(2), p. 183-193.
- Wuthnow, Robert, 1987, Meaning and Moral Order, Berkeley, University of California Press.
- Wuthnow, Robert, Hunter, James Davidson, Bergesen, Albert & Kurzweil, Edith, 1984, Cultural Analysis: The Work of Peter Berger, Mary Douglas, Michel Foucault and Jurgen Habermas, Boston, Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Zald, Mayer N., 1987, “The New Institutional Economies”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(3), p. 701-708.
- Zaret, David, 1986, The Heavenly Contract, Chicago, The University of Chicago Press.
- Zelizer, Viviana, 1985, Pricing the Priceless Child, New York, Basic Books.
- Zukin, Sharon & DiMaggio, Paul (eds.), 1986, “Structures of Capital”, double issue of Theory and Society, 15(1/2).
- Zunz, Olivier (ed.), 1985, Reliving the Past: The Worlds of Social History, Chapel Hill, The University of North Carolina.
Uploaded: 10/01/2021
Notes
-
[1]
First published in Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales (March, 1989) as « Intérêt, rationalité et culture : à propos d’un récent débat sur la théorie de l’action ».
For a recent debate on action theory, see J. S. Coleman, “Social Theory, Social Research, and a Theory of Action”, American Journal of Sociology, 91(6), 1986, p. 1309-1335; W. H. Sewell, Jr, “Theory of Action, Dialectic, and History: Comment on Coleman”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(1), 1987, p. 166-172; and J. S. Coleman, “Actors and Action in Social History and Social Theory: Reply to Sewell”, American Journal of Sociology, 93(1), 1987, p. 172-175. Full bibliographical references are given at the end of the article. -
[2]
In addition to Coleman’s text, the May 1986 issue of Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales included two other articles on the “State of Sociology Today” (i.e. American sociology): Immanuel Wallerstein (1986), “Marxisms as Utopias: Evolving Ideologies”, and Randall Collins (1986a), “Is 1980s Sociology in the Doldrums?” Collins’ text has also provoked a lively exchange, cf. Norman K. Denzin (1987a), “The Death of Sociology in the 1980s: Comment on Collins”, and Collins (1987), “Looking Forward or Looking Back? Reply to Denzin.”
-
[3]
Or, more precisely, the truncated and resolutely presentist representation that American sociology has formed of the utilitarians (Hume, Mill, Bentham and Adam Smith), largely under the impetus of Parsons, as Charles Camic (1979) shows. This philosophical filiation is actively claimed by Coleman (1986a, p. 1329), who sees in the “compatibility [of RAT] with the conceptual foundations that have underpinned much social thought since the political philosophers of natural law in the 17th century” one of the main merits of this paradigm and the instrument of a rapprochement that he deems necessary and beneficial between sociological theory, legal theory, and moral philosophy (cf. Coleman, 1974a).
-
[4]
Cf. Heath (1976) and the texts collected in Elster (1986).
-
[5]
Hardin (1982), Oliver (1980) and the classic of the genre by Mancur Olson (1965).
-
[6]
For example Hechter (1983, 1987).
-
[7]
See Knorr-Cetina (1981) and Wiley (1985, p. 189-195). The development of this “micro-interactionist tradition” specific to American social science is summarized by Randall Collins (1985, part 3). An overview of the main recent works in microsociology can be found in Adler, Adler and Fontana (1987) and Atkinson (1988). In addition to conversation analysis (e.g., Psathas, 1979; Heritage, 1985), it is in the sociology of emotions that the most vigorous developments are recorded (as witnessed by the creation in 1987 of a section of the American Sociological Association devoted to this specialty): for example, Kemper (1978), Shott (1979), Hochschild (1979, 1983), Denzin (1984), Lofland (1985) and the issue of the journal Symbolic Interaction edited by David D. Franks in the fall of 1985 (vol. 8, n° 2) devoted entirely to the “Sociology of Emotion”; in an anthropological vein, Lutz (1988).
-
[8]
It had been officially disowned by one of its founders, Peter Blau (1977a, 1977b), who turns to “all-macro” with Inequalitv and Heterogeneity. See also his “Preface” in the form of a volte-face to the re-edition of Exchange and Power in Social Life (Blau, 1986). This link between Coleman’s RAT and exchange theory is explicitly established by Homans (1987, 1988), who sees it as a special case of the behaviorism he has tirelessly promoted over the last three decades.
-
[9]
Przeworski (1985a, p. 379). This is also the view of Anthony Oberschall and Eric M. Leifer (1986, p. 233). On the economist side, see Hirschleifer (1985).
-
[10]
See Radnitzky and Bernholz (1987). The latest supplement to the American Journal of Sociology edited by Christopher Winship (a quantitative sociologist) and Sherwin Rosen (a Chicago School economist) entitled Organizations and Institutions: Sociological and Economic Approaches to the Analysis of Social Structures (1988) acknowledges this growing interpenetration of orthodox economics and sociology in the United States.
-
[11]
Williamson (1975, 1981), Moe (1984), Fama (1980), Pratt and Zeckhauser (1985). For an excellent critical synthesis of these currents, see Perrow (1986, chapter 7) and Francis, Turk and Willman (1983). In political sociology, rationalist positivism is led by William H. Riker and Peter C. Ordeshook (1973); see also Plott (1976), Barry (1978), and the still influential earlier works of Anthony Downs, James Buchanan, Gordon Tullock and Kenneth Arrow.
-
[12]
On the rationalist approach to social movement analysis, Obershall (1973), Fireman andGamson (1979), Olson (1982), Jenkins (1983), Tilly (1978, especially p. 24-37), and Popkin (1979). An analytical synopsis of current controversies in this area of investigation emphasizing the opposition between rational and historical-cultural or “identity” models can be found in Jean L. Cohen (1985). An interesting attempt to overcome this antinomy is made by James W. White (1988). The “monument” of rational family theory is without doubt Gary S. Becker’s A Treatise on the Family (1981), which has done more than any other work to legitimize “economic imperialism”, in the words of Kenneth Boulding (1969), in this field. See also the tellingly titled article by Ben-Porath (1980), “The F-Connection: Families, Friends, and Firms and the Organization of Exchange.” Diego Gambetta’s book, Did they jump or were they pushed? (1987) contains a synthesis of the claims of RAT in the sociology of education. For a sample of recent works in network theory which takes as its object the structures of observable relations between social or organizational positions and more or less explicitly implements a rational or utilitarian conception of action, see Burt (1982), Laumann and Knoke (1987), Wellman and Berkowitz (1988).
-
[13]
Cf. Granovetter (1973, 1974) and the seminal article “Economy Action and Social Structure: The Problem of Embeddedness” (Granovetter, 1985); the work of Harrison White (1970, 1981), Leifer (1985), Powell (1985), Sabel (198, p. 4), Stark (1986), Berg (1981), as well as the articles collected by Zukin and DiMaggio (1986); also Tilly (1984b, on Mancur Olson) and Zald (1987, on Oliver Williamson). On the emergence of economic sociology as an autonomous problematic, see Swedberg, Himmelstrand and Brulin (1987) and, in a more idiosyncratic vein, Stinchcombe (1983).
-
[14]
On “voluntarist nominalism,” see Hinckle and Hinckle (1980); on “instrumental positivism” in American sociology, Bryant (1985, chapter 5).
-
[15]
See Hirsch, Michaels and Friedman (1987), and the more ambivalent view of Oberschall and Leifer (1985, p. 251).
-
[16]
The University of Chicago can legitimately claim to be the Mecca of Rational Action Theory: it has several of the most prominent representatives of RAT on its campus (James Coleman, Gary S. Becker, George Stigler, Jon Elster, and Adam Przeworski, among others). Its sociology department is the only one in the country to offer doctoral training in RAT, which includes a battery of courses specifically designed to systematize and disseminate its teaching. James Coleman and Gary Becker conduct an annual closed seminar on “Rational Models in the Social Sciences” that is nationally renowned and brings together, two evenings a month, the Rats of the Sociology, Political Science, and Economics departments. Jon Elster is the director of the newly established Center for the Study of Ethics, Rationality, and Society, where the best representatives of utilitarian subjectivism from all continents come together. A journal dedicated to the promotion of methodological individualism and deductivist rationalism has been created under the direction of James Coleman, entitled Rationalitv and Society, the first issue of which was published in June 1989.
-
[17]
See Bourdieu (1980, p. 71-83), for a critique of the ‘imaginary anthropology’ that is at the root of Sartrean phenomenology and Elster’s version of RAT.
-
[18]
The best overall introduction to this current is the collection of texts presented by John E. Roemer (1986) under the title Analytical Marxism. Also published in this series are Jon Elster, Making Sense of Marx (1985); Adam Przeworski, Capitalism and Social Democracy (1985b); and Michael Taylor (cd.), Rationalitv and Revolution (1988). Other important books of Analytical Marxism are G.A. Cohen, Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence (1978); the ultra-mathematical technical tracts of John E. Roemer, Analytical Foundations of Marxian Economic Theory (1981) and A General Theory of Exploitation and Class (1982a), and the popular textbook for the undergraduate market, Free To Lose: An Introduction to Marxist Economic Philosophy (Roemer, 1988); Philippe Van Parijs, Evolutionary Explanation in the Social Sciences (1981a); and Erik Olin Wright, Classes (1985). Two debates around the theses of the Analytical Marxists can be found in issue 4, volume 11, 1982, (on Marxism, functionalism and game theory) and issue 5, volume 15, 1986, (on the transition to socialism) of Theory and Society and in issue 3, volume 11, 1982, of Politics and Society (on Roemer’s exploitation theory).
-
[19]
The series “Studies in Marxism and Social Theory” edited by G. A. Cohen, Jon Elster and John Roemer at Cambridge University Press and Éditions de la Maison des Sciences et de l’Homme is presented in these terms: “The books in this series are intended to exemplify a new paradigm in the study of Marxist social theory. Rather than adopting a dogmatic or purely exegetical approach, they will examine and develop the theory inaugurated by Marx in the light of historical experience since then, using the tools of non-Marxist social science and philosophy. It is hoped that this will free Marxist thought from the increasingly discredited methods and presuppositions which are still widely regarded as essential to it, and that what is true and important in Marxism will thus be more firmly established.”
-
[20]
Roemer (1986, p. 2-3). Further on: “In seeking to give behavior the micro-foundations that Marxists regard as characteristic of capitalism, I believe that the instruments par excellence are the models based on rational choice: general equilibrium theory, game theory, and the arsenal of modeling techniques developed by neo-classical economics” (ibid., p. 192).
-
[21]
“To understand scientific explanation or the notion of causality, the structure of intentional action or that of social interaction, knowledge of analytical philosophy is now indispensable” (Elster, An English Marxism: About a New Interpretation of Historical Materialism, 1981, p. 746). The following passage, which closes Elster’s “Critical Note on G.A. Cohen’s analytical reading of Marx,” gives an idea of the hyperbole and rhetorical effects aimed at creating an impression of radical innovation that characterize many of the mutual comments that practitioners of Analytical Marxism grace each other with regularly – and whose metaphorical schemes (pure/stagnant air, life/death, rare/common, high/low, etc.) suffice to express the intellectual height that they assign to their collective enterprise: “With his rigorous book, each page of which deserves to be commented on passionately, [Cohen] has brought us into a landscape that we did not know. The air we breathe is no longer the stagnant atmosphere of the endless scholastic discussions that nearly ruined Marxism. It is the air of the mountains; it is scarce, but we can see clearly and far” (ibid., p. 756). For another example, see Van Parijs’ (1986-87) celebration of Roemer and Wright’s class theory in an article squarely entitled “A Revolution in Class Theory.”
-
[22]
We borrow this term from Frank Parkin (1979, p. 10).
-
[23]
Partly as a result of a hysteresis effect, RAT has not yet entered the recognized scholarly taxonomies of the universe of sociological theories in America and Britain (e.g., it is absent as such from the collection assembled by Giddens and Turner, 1987, Social Theory Today).
-
[24]
In addition to the collection edited by Cohen, Roemer, and Elster mentioned above, note the series “Studies in Rationality and Social Change” edited by Jon Elster and Gudmunt Hernes at Cambridge University Press and the “California Series on Social Choice and Political Economy” published by University of California Press under the editorship of political scientists Brian Barry, Robert H. Bates and Samuel L. Popkin.
-
[25]
This article represents both the culmination of his earlier work (as evidenced by the series of public papers from 1964 to 1983 – more than a third of which were published in economics books and journals – collected in J.S. Coleman, Individual Interests and Collective Action (1986c, in Jon Elster’s “Studies in Rationality and Social Change” series) and the programmatic introduction to Foundations of Social Theory. No introduction is needed here to James Coleman, author of a considerable body of work, including nearly 150 articles and some twenty books, including The Adolescent Society (1961); the famous “Coleman Report” on equal opportunity in American schools, which was the basis for the federal policy of racial desegregation of schools (Coleman et al., 1966); The Mathematics of Collective Action (1973); Power and the Structure of Society (1974b); The Asymmetric Society (1982); and, most recently, Public and Private High Schools: The Impact of Communities (Coleman and Hoffer 1986).
-
[26]
Because of the institutional and intellectual gap between theory and practice in the United States, and in particular the representation of the former as an autonomous “specialty” essentially of pure conceptual exegesis (as reflected in the indigenous term theorizing). Parsons remains, against all odds, the cardinal reference in the American sociological field for whoever wants to ensure the status of theoretical discourse to his subject. It is not surprising, therefore, that the fiftieth anniversary of the publication of his first book, The Structure of Social Action, in 1937, was celebrated with great pomp and circumstance at the annual conference of the American Sociological Association in 1987, The session was reminiscent of a totemic ritual in many ways and included Bernard Barber, Harold Garfinkel (both of whom were trained by Parsons at Harvard), Jeffrey Alexander (who is now trying to rekindle the flame, cf. Alexander 1988c) and Jonathan Turner.
-
[27]
It may seem paradoxical that Coleman should look to Parsons for the “promising beginnings” of the utilitarian theory of action that he intends to develop, since we know that the voluntarism that the Harvard master placed at the epicenter of his sociology is defined precisely by an irreducible opposition to utilitarianism. The fact that Coleman does not note this antinomy, or rather, gives it as a continuity by confusing Parsons’ voluntarism with Benthamian purposiveness, strongly suggests the tactical character of the discursive reference to Parsons (even if unconsciously so). This paradox, while only apparent, is reminiscent of the strategy of legitimization employed by Parsons himself half a century earlier in his interpretation of Durkheim and Weber, which, we recall, consisted, by means of a fictitious retro-projection, in presenting his own theory as the systematization that makes explicit an “involuntary and unnoticed” convergence between them and advances towards a normative conception of action, which resolves the eternal Hobbesian problem of social order.
-
[28]
Amartya K. Sen (1977) offers a succinct exposition and stimulating critique of these anthropological presuppositions in his article “Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economies.”
-
[29]
Coleman (1986a, p. 1312; 1986b, p. 347 and p. 360-363). French readers will easily recognize the problematic of ‘methodological individualism’, e.g. Boudon (1979, see postscript) and Padioleau (1986), even if the latter struggles to distinguish the French version of the RAT from its American by shamelessly – and somewhat ungraciously – calling the latter ‘rustic utilitarianism’ (p. 210).
-
[30]
In a paper presented at an economics and management conference on the inadequacies of the utilitarian model of action (and published in the Journal of Business under the title “Psychological Structure and Social Structure in Economic Models”, 1986d), Coleman urges participants to focus on the micro-macro step rather than wasting their time complexifying the “micro-foundations of purposive action”: “It is the defects in the apparatus which effects the transition from the level of the individual actor to that of the system’s behavior which lays the most hope for progress” for economic theory, not the revision of the scheme of rational action which underlies it. See also his plenary lecture at the Annual Conference of the American Economic Association, “Introducing Social Structure into Economic Analysis” (Coleman, 1984): “It is not by abandoning the conception of rational action of individuals” that social science will be advanced “but by modifying the organizational assumptions that translate individual action into collective or systemic action.”
-
[31]
In an earlier paper (“Microfoundations and Macrosocial Theory”), Coleman (1986b) proposes a slightly different typology of aggregation mechanisms that includes, in addition to markets, authoritarian organizations, and norms, social choice rules (e.g. electoral systems) and collective behaviors (e.g. panics or rumors).
-
[32]
See his articles “Social Structure and the Emergence of Norms Among Rational Actors”, and “Norms as Social Capital” (Coleman, 1986e; 1987c).
-
[33]
For various graphical variants of this basic scheme, see Coleman (1987b). The example reproduced here is meant to model Weber’s thesis in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.
-
[34]
Cf. his reinvention of the concept of social capital in Social Capital in the Creation of Human Capital (Coleman, 1988a), and the article “Free Riders and Zealots: The Role of Social Networks” (Coleman, 1988b).
-
[35]
To extend it, one can read with great profit the work of Stanley Lieberson (1985), in which one of the major practitioners of the canonical methods of multivariate analysis subjects it to a piercing methodological critique, which was the subject of a very instructive debate in the 1987 volume of Sociological Methodology.
-
[36]
William H. Sewell Jr. (not to be confused with his father William H. Sewell, an ultra-quantitative sociologist of the Wisconsin School who was one of the initiators of status attainment research, and whose influence continues to be felt long after his retirement, since his protégé and heir, Aage Soerensen, was recently entrusted with the direction of the sociology department of Harvard University in desperate search of hard legitimacy: On Sewell Sr’s career, read Sewell, 1988) is first and foremost an excellent specialist in French social history. His doctoral dissertation in history at the University of California at Berkeley in 1971 was on “The Structure of the Working Class in Marseilles in the Mid-19th Century” and was published as The Men and Women of Marseilles. 1820-1870 (Sewell, 1985a). William H. Sewell Jr. now holds the prestigious joint chair of sociology and history vacated by Charles Tilly at the University of Michigan in Ann Arbor. Among his most important publications are Social Change and the Rise of Working-Class Politics in Nineteenth-Century Marseilles (Sewell, 1974a); Etat, Corps, and Ordre: Some Notes on the Social Vocabulary of the French Old Regime (1974b); Corporations Republicaines: The Revolutionary Idiom of Parisian Workers in 1848 (1979); Work and Revolution in France: The Language of Labor from the Old Régime to 1848 (1980); La confraternité des prolétaires : conscience de classe sous la monarchie de Juillet (1981); Artisans, Factory Workers, and the Formation of the French Working Class, 1789-1848 (1986); and Uneven Development, the Autonomy of Politics, and the Dockworkers of Nineteenth-Century Marseilles (1988).
-
[37]
Collins (1986a, p. 1346). See Calhoun (1987) for a comparison with England, where there is a similar flowering of historical sociology (evidenced by the recent launch of the journal Historical Sociology), but mainly under the leadership of historians, and Sztompka’s (1986) remarks in “The Renaissance of Historical Orientation in Sociology.”
-
[38]
Portes (1976) provides an excellent overview of the subfield of macro developmental sociology around this time.
-
[39]
Among others, W. J. Wilson (1980), Lieberson (1980), and Morawska (1985) on ethnic and racial relations; on the state, the book edited by Rueschemeyer, Evans, and Skocpol (1985) marks the ascendancy of the neoinstitutionalist approach (or “state-centered theories” as opposed to “society-centered theories”); also Poggi (1978), Quadagno (1988), Weir, Orloff and Skocpol (1988). Progress in this area of research can be followed via the quarterly States and Social Structures Newsletter published by the Social Science Research Council in New York.
-
[40]
On Anglo-American work in the historical sociology of class, see Roy’s (1984) useful synopsis. Some of the more prominent recent works include Sabel (1984), Burawoy (1985), Katznelson (1981), Katnelson and Zolberg (1986), Moore (1978), Aminzade (1981), Calhoun (1982), Wilentz (1984), Levine (1984), McNall (1988), and Haydu (1988).
-
[41]
Tilly, Tilly and Tilly (1975), Paige (1975), Trimberger (1978), Skocpol (1979), Bonnell (1983), Hunt (1984), Traugott (1985), Tilly (1985), and Burke (1988).
-
[42]
Notably Sarfatti-Larson (1977), Starr (1982), Geison (1984), Rueschemeyer (1973; 1986).
-
[43]
Wallerstein (1974; 1979; 1984), Hechter (1975), Chirot (1976), Block (1977), Evans (1978), Mann (1986), Hall (1985), see Wallerstein (1987) and Chirot and Hall (1982), respectively, for a synthetic presentation and a review of the so-called “world-system” theory, as well as the annual “Political Economy of the World System” series published by Sage under Wallerstein’s direction.
-
[44]
In cultural-historical sociology, we may mention, to limit ourselves to the principal works of the recent period, Zelizer (1985), Zaret (1986), Griswold (1986), Laitin (1986), Hunt (1984), Patterson (1984), Corrigan and Sayer (1985), Abercrombie et al., (1980), Sennett (1977), and historian Herbert G. Gutman’s remarkable posthumous collection of essays, Power and Culture (1987).
-
[45]
Notably Hall and Jefferson (1976), Hebdige (1979), and Willis (1977), widely cited and used, especially in teaching.
-
[46]
The influence of Geertz’s semiological conception of culture (e.g. 1974) on Sewell dates from their common stay at the University of Chicago in the early 1970s. Later, Sewell spent several years at the Center for Advanced Studies in Princeton at the invitation of the latter. On the impact of Geertz’s symbolic anthropology on historical research in America, see Walters (1980); also Darnton (1984, p. 9-13 and p. 296-303), and Bourdieu, Chartier and Darnton (1985). A critical discussion of the thorny methodological and theoretical problems posed by Geertzian thick description can be found in Roseberry (1982), Shankman (1984), Crapanzano (1986), and in Schneider’s (1987) insightful article, “Culture-as-Text in the Work of Clifford Geertz.” On the interpretive current more generally, Rabinow and Sullivan (1979).
-
[47]
This is one of the theses that Goffman (1974) develops in his critique of interactionism and ethnomethodology with the notion of “framework-analysis”.
-
[48]
Sewell (1987, p. 168). For Albert Hirschman (1982, p. 79), “a more general criticism that can be levelled at Olson’s analysis – and at much of economic decision theory in general – is that the subjects, while effective and often ingenious and tortuous, are devoid of history.” Timothy Luke (1985, p. 70), a reasoned proponent of RAT, agrees that it logically presupposes “uneducated, unhistoricized, depoliticized and unsocialized” individuals. Adam Przeworski (1985a, p. 381) himself recognizes that “the ontological assumptions of the rational choice model – and especially the assumption of undifferentiated, unchanging and unrelated ‘individuals’ – are untenable.”
-
[49]
As demonstrated, among others, by Elias (1973), Abercrombie et al., Foucault (1975; 1976), Rosaldo (1980), Carrithers, Collins and Lukes (1985).
-
[50]
Sewell (1987, p. 169, note 2). Anthony Giddens (1977) has established that, in any case, the Hobbesian problem never occupied the central place in the thought of the founding fathers that it does in orthodox American theory. We know, moreover, since C. B. Macpherson’s classic study, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (1962) that the political and social presuppositions of the Hobbesian vision of the social order are more related to the economic and social organization of English mercantilism of the 17th century than to a hypothetical “state of nature.”
-
[51]
His reaction is to be compared with the harsh criticisms he formulates elsewhere against the interactionist approach of Gusfield and the comparative method employed by Skocpol and Orloff (Coleman, 1986b).
-
[52]
See Van Parijs (1981b) for a summary of these distinctions.
-
[53]
Van Parijs (1981b, p. 312). Here Russell Hardin goes so far as to conclude, in his article “Difficulties with the Notion of Economic Rationality” (1983, p. 465), that “The individual rationality supposedly at the root of economic explanations at the societal level is essentially a chimera.” Similarly. Douglas (1986, p. 102) concedes that while individuals make decisions, it is institutions that define the classifications between which they choose.
-
[54]
Hollis (1987). And one could quote Wittgenstein (1965), for whom “At the end of reasons comes persuasion.”
-
[55]
Winch (1958). The main moments of this long controversy which continues to this day are gathered in the two volumes edited by Wilson (1970) and Hollis and Lukes (1982). On Rationalitätstreit in the philosophy of science, one can read with profit the original work of Paul A. Roth, Meaning and Method in the Social Sciences: A Case for Methodological Pluralism (1987).
-
[56]
Gilligan (1982) and Benhabib and Cornell (1987) and the immense literature that has developed at an exponential rate in recent years at the intersection of critical theory, feminism, and historiography, from which Joan Scott’s recent book Gender and the Politics of History (1988) stands out.
-
[57]
M. Burawoy, “Mythological Individualism”, lecture delivered at Harvard University in May 1988 on the occasion of a Symposium in honor of Parsons.
-
[58]
According to a study by Nobel Prize winner Wassily Leontief (reported by Hirsch et al., 1987, p. 330-31), more than half of the articles published in the American Economic Review between 1977 and 1981 relied on pure mathematical models without containing any observational data, while less than 0,5% of the authors had made the effort to produce new data. To Coleman’s credit, however, there is no such disproportion between theoretical effort and empirical observation, in contrast to the Analytical Marxists (except Przeworski and Wright), who, to say the least, do not bother with observational data. This is in violation of the principles laid down by Marx who recommended, in The German Ideology: “Empirical observation must in each separate instance bring out empirically and without any mystification and speculation, the connection of the social and political structure with production. The social structure and the State are continually evolving out of the life-process of definite individuals, but of individuals, not as they appear in their own or other people’s imagination, but as they really are: i.e., as they operate, produce materially, and hence as they work under definite material limits, presuppositions and conditions independent of their will” (Marx and Engels, 1970, p. 46-47, emphasis added).
-
[59]
See Hirschman (1986, chapter 4), Sen (1977), Lieberstein (1976; 1979, especially p. 493-496 on the problems posed by the maximization postulate), Sen and Williams (1982), and Miller and Williams (1982). According to Spiro Latsis (1972), the “research program” of neoclassical microeconomics has been in a phase of degeneration for quite some time.
-
[60]
“Rational choice theory may well be nothing more than an ‘ideology’ that merely transcribes into the more acceptable theoretical language of the individual market decision the harsh reality of managerially imposed decisions” (Luke, 1985, p. 77).
-
[61]
Lash and Urry (1984) make it clear that Elster’s postulate of individualism and game theory are an ontology of the social, not simply a methodology. The function of political denial of the RAT has been brilliantly noted by Albert Hirschman (1982, p. 78-79): “Now it must be recalled that Mancur Olson proclaimed the impossibility of collective action (just as Daniel Bell proclaimed the ‘end of ideology’) at the precise moment when the Western world was about to be all but engulfed by an unprecedented wave of public movements. […] It seems to me paradoxically conceivable that the success of Olson’s book owes something to its having been contradicted by the subsequently evolving events. Once the latter had safely run their course, the many people who found them deeply upsetting could go back to The Logic of Collective Action and find in it good and reassuring reasons why those collective actions of the sixties should never have happened in the first place, were perhaps less real than they seemed and would be most unlikely to recur. Thus the book did not suffer from being contradicted by subsequent events; rather, it gained by actively contradicting them and became a great success among those who found these events intolerable and totally aberrant.” It is to this function of derealization of the social that the normative, even prescriptive dimension of the RAT responds, noted or claimed by many authors, like Luke (1985, p. 98), Downs (for whom the political RAT “occupies a twilight zone between normative models and prescriptive models,” 1957, p. 31) and Van Parijs (1981a, p. 305). Gibson (1977) goes so far as to argue that no non-normative conception of rationality is philosophically tenable.
-
[62]
For example, Boudon (1984), but also Jon Elster (1979), who sees Morgenstern and Weber as the two masters of rational theory.
-
[63]
Weber (1978, p. 6-7). On the multiple meanings of the concepts of rationality and rationalization in Weber, see Brubaker (1984) and Sica (1988), who has recently subjected Weber’s bias in favor of rationality to close scrutiny. This Weberian distinction between model and reality finds a fruitful extension in Alfred Schutz’s (1953; 1970, p. 125-159) opposition between “scientific rationality” and “common sense rationality,” an opposition taken up and elaborated empirically by Garfinkel and the ethnomethodologists, whose breaching experiments (Garfinkel, 1967, p. 35-75) demonstrate better than all the speeches that social life would simply be intolerable and impossible if social agents actually behaved in the manner of rational actors of the RAT.